INTRODUCTION 1
PART I :
OUR COMMON HUMANITIES - THE GROUNDING FOR A
DIALOGICAL AND INTERCULTURAL HUMAN RIGHTS IDEAL 9
CHAPTER I : The Requirements for Genuine Intercultural Dialogue 13
I. The Rhetoric of the Dialogue
II. The Paradigm of the Encompassing of the Contrary 15
III. The Dialogical Approach : Dialogical versus Dialectical Dialogue 17
IV. The Diatopical Approach -Diatopical Hermeneutics
20
CHAPTER II : Crystallizing and Modelling our Common Humanities 23
I. Thinking God - Thinking Law - Legal archetypes and logics 24
II. Crystallizing our Common Humanities 26
1. Identification
2. Differentiation 29
3. Submission 31
4. The Indian Archetype 34
III. Modelling our Common Humanities as a Platform
for Intercultural Dialogue 36
1. The Subject of Human Rights 38
2. The Different Social Orders
3. The Legal Tripod 39
4. A Platform for Intercultural Dialogue on Human Rights 40
PART II :
OUR HUMAN COMMUNITY :
TOWARDS A PLURAL AND PRAXIS ORIENTED
HUMAN RIGHTS PARADIGM 45
CHAPTER III : Community - A Paradigm for
Intercultural Human Rights' Thought 48
I. The Modern Paradigm and its Transformations
1. The Modern Paradigm 49
2. A Change of Perspective : From a Legal System's
to a Legal Actors' View ? 52
II. The Human Rights' Community - A New Paradigm
for Human Rights' Thought 57
1. The Scope of the Paradigmatic Change
2. The Human Rights' Community 60
CHAPTER IV : Operationalizing the Human Rights' Community
through the Concept of Game 65
I. The Concept of Game in Legal Theory
II. The Jeu de l'oie or Legal Monopoly 69
PART III :
TOWARDS A DIANTHROPOLOGICAL
PRAXIS OF HUMAN RIGHTS 71
CHAPTER V : A Dialogue with the Spiritual Traditions in order to Enrich
our Picture of Man 83
I. Spiritual Traditions and the Human 85
1. What are Spiritual Traditions and what could they Contribute
to the Human Rights' Discussion?
2. Man Seen through the Prism of the Spiritual Traditions 90
II. Enriching the Notion of Dignity by the Spiritual Teachings:
Towards a Homeomorphic and Communitarian Picture of Man 93
CHAPTER VI : Towards a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights 99
I. The Cosmotheandric Intuition 100
II. Love, Wisdom and Peace as the Cornerstones of
a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights 102
III. Towards a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights 105
CONCLUSION :
BUILDING A COMMON FUTURE
AS BRIGHT AND COLOURED
AS THE RAINBOW 107
ANNEXES 112
BIBLIOGRAPHY 129
Are human rights universal, a cultural
invariant, that is to say, part of a global culture ? (...) Because the question
of universality is the answer to an aspiration of completeness, and because
each culture 'situates' such an aspiration around ultimate values and universal
validity, different aspirations to different ultimate values in different
cultures will lead to isomorphic concerns which, given the adequate hermeneutical
procedures, may become mutually intelligible and mutually translatable. At
best it is even possible to achieve a mixture and interpenetration of concerns
and concepts. The more equal power relations among cultures are, the more
probable it is that such
mestizaje might occur.
A balanced cross-cultural mestizaje of concerns and concepts is the
multicultural correspondent of single-culture universality. (...) alongside
the dominant discourse and practice of human rights conceived as a globalized
Western localism, a counterhegemonic discourse and practice of human rights
conceived as a cosmopolitan politics has been developing. The central task
of emancipatory politics of our time, in this domain, consists in transforming
the conceptualization and practice of human rights from a globalized localism
into a cosmopolitan project. (de SOUSA SANTOS 1995 : 337-339)
In
this thesis we will try to take up the challenge de SOUSA SANTOS is presenting
to us. We will try to make a contribution to the emergence of an intercultural
mestizaje of Human Rights.
What is at stake ? In my opinion,
it is to enable the emergence of a universally accepted and efficient Human
Rights' system. Or it is rather, as I will develop in this thesis, the building
of a working Human Rights' Community.
We
seem to be invited to rethink the contemporary paradigm of Human Rights'
thought and practice as it seems less and less able to respond to the challenges
facing us. First, Human Rights are de facto not universal. They are not
universally guaranteed to every human being. They are violated, and often
grossly, all over the world. Second, even their abstract universality is
more and more challenged. This is especially the case through their increasing
questioning by non-western cultural traditions. The Vienna World Conference
on Human Rights of 1993 provided a good illustration of this trend. There
the western character of the universal declaration of Human Rights of 1948
has been criticised by a group of Asian, African and Middle East countries.
It has for example been advanced that collective rights should get their
place next to individual rights, economical rights next to political rights,
and that rights should be counterbalanced by corresponding duties. It has
been argued that these demands express specific civilisational values (LE
ROY 1997a : 1-2).
Thus posing our western theory
and practice of Human Rights as universal without further questioning, becomes
a less and less tenable and intellectually satisfying position. Nevertheless
it is as untenable to deny that by its development of Human Rights through
its culture and history, the western tradition has touched upon something
universal. The respect for human life, the ideal of human fraternity (see
articles 1 and 3 of the declaration of 1948) cannot be reduced to a western
invention. They bear something more, plunging its roots in the most profound
depths of human experience.
Engaging into an intercultural
dialogue on Human Rights, trying to achieve a mestizaje of Human Rights
should thus not be interpreted as the taking of a completely relativistic
standpoint, or as the negating of any universality of Human Rights. Engaging
in intercultural dialogue on Human Rights should in my mind rather be seen
as a constructive, rather than as a destructive endeavour. The point is not
to deconstruct the western approach by refuting its universality. The point
is rather to enrich this approach through different cultural perspectives
in order to progressively achieve an intercultural tradition of Human Rights,
a mestizaje of Human Rights. PANIKKAR (1984a : 30) can help us to
illustrate this point of view :
Human Rights are one window through
which one particular culture envisages a just human order for its individuals.
But those who live in that culture do not see the window. For this they need
the help of another culture which sees through another window. Now I assume
that he human landscape as seen through the one window is both similar to
and different from the vision of the other. If this is the case, should we
smash the windows and make of the many portals a single gaping aperture -
with the consequent danger of structural collapse - , or should we enlarge
the viewpoints as much as possible and, most of all, make people aware that
there are - and have to be - a plurality of windows? This latter option would
be the one in favor of a healthy pluralism.
Engaging in healthy pluralism
is what lies at the core of our whole present endeavour. We will strongly
refuse to take the look through the western window for the only and all
encompassing view. And we will also strongly refuse to engage into absolute
cultural relativism. Healthy pluralism demands us to recognize plurality.
But it also demands us to keep in mind its underlying unity. It respects
and takes seriously all cultural universalisms, which is to say the specific
cultural ways to access to the universal, but at the same time it emphasises
that an intercultural universality, a mestizaje of Human Rights can
only emerge and can only be entertained by the intercultural dialogue of
these different universalisms. Our standpoint is thus neither universalistic
nor relativistic. It is pluralistic.
The problem with the universalistic position is that it is highly ethnocentric, as it turns in an undue manner values and conceptions of the society of belonging into universal ones (TODOROV 1992b : 21-22). Dialogue thus becomes impossible. Indeed dialogue is first of all duo-logue (PANIKKAR 1979 : 346). It demands respect for the other and for the other's perspective. Therefore what necessarily arises out of the universalistic position is a monologue, which is potentially oppressive to those who do not share our values and conceptions. In the Human Rights' context the universalistic position leads to a globalized Western localism which is doubly counterproductive in our search for universality, or for an interculturally shared outlook on Human Rights. First it does not permit the mutual enrichment of our and the other cultures. By negating the voice of the other we cannot learn from him or her, nor can we fecundate him or her. Sharing, which is giving and taking, is only possible through the recognition of the other. Without recognition, no sharing. And without sharing, no reaching of a consensus, no building of a common future. Therefore, second, the universalistic position takes us from a logic of complementarity and of exchange to a logic of exclusion and of power. This favours particularistic withdrawals which can partly be seen as defensive reactions against the western steam-roller (LATOUCHE 1991 : 8, ABOU 1992 : 16). It makes the building of a Human Rights' Community impossible. Thus the universalistic position instead of strengthening the universality of Human Rights rather turns out to weaken it by cutting off through exclusion its most fundamental basements : the different peoples of the world.
The problem with the relativistic
position is that it absolutizes differences and completely forgets about
our common human nature and condition. It is so deeply stuck in our
differences that it only sees the differences and forgets
completely about the our. The relativistic position emphasizes
so much the different perspectives that it forgets about the common horizon.
Reaching any kind of universality becomes in that view impossible. Each culture
has its own values, conceptions and world view which cannot be challenged,
and not even understood or even questioned by other cultures. The picture
is the one of a fundamental Other with whom no dialogue is
conceivable, with whom no mutual enrichment is possible. The best to be expected
is mere more or less harmonious coexistence. But no real living together,
no mutual understanding, no sharing, no building of a common future seems
possible. Such a relativistic outlook can either lead to an imposition of
one's own values on the others (which comes very close to the universalism
described above) or in the case of an acknowledgement of an absolute right
to difference can lead, in the words of ABOU (1992 : 34-35), to a right
to confinement (droit à l'enfermement), or even
to a right to oppression (droit à l'oppression)
or to a right to death (droit à la mort).
The way we therefore choose,
is the way of healthy pluralism. This way entails a fundamental
paradigmatic change in Human Rights' thought. As de SOUSA SANTOS notes it
is not enough in a period of paradigmatic transition to criticize the old
paradigms, new paradigms must be built :
The truth is that, after centuries of modernity, the absence of a future cannot be filled out by either the past or the present.The lack of future is but an empty future.
We must, therefore, reinvent the future by opening up a new horizon of possibilities mapped out by new radical alternatives. Merely to criticize the dominant paradigm, though crucial is not enough. We must also define the emergent paradigm, this being the really important and difficult task. (...)
The only route, it seems to me, is utopia.
By utopia I mean the exploration by imagination of new modes of human possibility
and styles of will, and the confrontation by imagination of the necessity
of whatever exists-just because it exists- on behalf of something radically
better that is worth fighting for, and to which humanity is fully
entitled. (de SOUSA
SANTOS 1995 : 479)
Let us thus engage in
utopia, or rather in heterotopia which Rather
than the invention of a place elsewhere or nowhere is a
radical displacement within the same place : ours. (de SOUSA SANTOS
1995 : 481) . We may not use the term heterotopia exactly in
de SOUSA SANTOS' sense. But what is important to me is the idea of the
radical displacement within the same place : ours. By walking
on the path of healthy pluralism we do not intend to leave this
world. We will rather try to see it in a different perspective enabling us
to stand up to the contemporary challenges facing us. This new perspective
is not a perspective out of the blue, separated from our past and radically
different from it. Rather the displacement will result from the putting into
dialogue of our perspective with other perspectives. It will be the result
of a building on our past through its enrichment by our present, which becomes
more and more intercultural and thus also demands us to build on the other
cultures' pasts and presents. Healthy pluralism is thus based on mutual dialogue
permitting us respectively to discover the others and ourselves, to discover
their and our past and present, and to build together a common future.
In
this thesis the path of and to healthy pluralism will lead us through three
stations, an examination of Common Humanities, Human Community and
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights. In my eyes each of these concepts
constitutes a specific pluralistic paradigm for intercultural Human Rights'
Thought. The first, Common Humanities, is related to the plural basement
in which our intercultural Human Rights' approach could be rooted. The second,
Human Community deals with the plural place (intellectual and practical)
where this intercultural Human Rights' approach could unfold. The third,
Dianthropological Praxis, deals with the maybe emerging myth which could
underlie and sustain our intercultural Human Rights' thought and praxis,
and which could provide it with a horizon, and thus with meaning.
Although Common Humanities,
Human Community and Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights are three distinct
paradigms, they can only really be understood in their interrelation and
interconnectedness. They are the three paradigms making up the broader paradigm
of a healthy pluralism in intercultural Human Rights' thought. And they should
not be seen as making up this broader paradigm in their mechanical juxtaposition.
Rather those three paradigms are organically interrelated. They are the organic
parts of the organic whole we call healthy pluralism. The whole, and thus
the mutual interrelation of its parts, define the parts as much as the parts
define the whole. This should be kept in mind in order to avoid
miscomprehensions. It does nevertheless of course not exclude that each paradigm
can be individually enlightened, criticised and enriched, as much as the
broader paradigm they constitute.
This is not the place to go
into a detailed account of these paradigms. They will be extensively developed
in the three parts of this thesis. At this point I will only make some brief
reflections on them to familiarize the reader with these concepts and to
prevent possible misconceptions.
If
I have chosen to speak of Common Humanities as the basis for
an intercutural approach to Human Rights, it is to draw attention to the
paradox of our human condition, characterized both by human unity and by
human diversity, and to emphasize the equal importance of both for the building
of an intercultural mestizaje of Human Rights. We are alike and though
we are different. We could even say that to some extent we are alike precisely
in that we are different. All cultures share a common human condition, which
is partially characterized by their need to provide, or to find, meaning
to their existences. This need is fulfilled through the construction of
particular world views and by the invention of related social organizations.
We can thus say that we share our world in our Common Humanities,
in our particular ways to be human. There is a common horizon, the
Common in Common Humanities and also the
Human of Humanities, and at the same time there are
the different perspectives recalled by the plural form of
Humanities. In Part I we will thus try to give an overview of
our different humanities. We will also try to see how they can
engage in intercultural dialogue. And we will show how this intercultural
dialogue can allow for the discovery of our Common Humanities,
by shedding light on what we share as well as on what differentiates us.
Part I will enable us to get a broader perspective on our human condition
and on Human Rights than if we had contented ourselves with only
looking through our own cultural window. And it will permit us
to move from an exclusionary to a complementary logic.
In
Part II, on Human Community, we will try to think of how the insights we
may have gained in Part I could be put into practice. To do so we will have
to acknowledge pluralism in the legal field. This in turn will demand to
abandon a solely theoretical point of view on law. Law is not
only what the books say - it is also what people do. LE ROY (1994a : 29)
even said :
To think of law, is first of all not to trust what specialists say about it. CLAUZEWITH, the founding father of modern strategy, said that war was to important to be left to soldiers alone. Some of us anthropologists say : 'law is too important to be left to lawyers alone'.
Law, is not what the lawyers say about it, it is what the actors make out
of it. It is what the citizens make out of it. It is the practices of the
citizens which permit us to measure the efficacy of law. Law is not in the
texts, it is in the practices. -1-
We will thus have to take into account the actors' perspective and emphasize
legal praxis. We speak of Human Rights' praxis in order to
emphasize an approach favouring a Human Rights' legal context that makes
sense to the concerned actors in their theory and practice. This emphasis
on praxis is a reaction against the predominant poietic,
instrumental, view of Human Rights. This view sees Human Rights rather as
the technical tools of a Human Rights' system. Talking of Human Community
or Human Rights' Community is thus intended to invite us to leave a systemic
approach to Human Rights, characterized by a single point of view and a rather
instrumental outlook on law, in favour of a Communitarian approach characterized
by the existence of a multiplicity of view points and of their dialogue,
and by the emphasis on praxis.
Although COTTERRELL develops a somewhat different kind of approach to Law's
Community as we do here by presenting the Human Community, our approach has
nonetheless a lot in common with his and the following quotation gives a
fair impression of the stakes of our own endeavour:
(...) as many writers have suggested,
we need to rethink the concept of law itself in pluralistic terms. That can
only be done theoretically with any rigour by developing some such notion
as that of community. The long established 'modern' view has been that law
is in essence the law of the nation state. But transnational law (...) is
assuming increased importance (...) So also is the idea of autonomous or
semi-autonomous regulation of regions, localities, groups and enterprises.
(...) Equally, there are now aspirations for more diverse and, in some sense
'local' processes of creating, interpreting and applying regulation. The
aim is to make this regulation more morally meaningful, closer to the lived
experience of citizens, than much state law.
(COTTERRELL 1996c : 1)
To
avoid misunderstandings from the start as to my paradigm of Community, it
may be important to stress that it does not directly refer to
communitarian thought, although the acceptance of this paradigm
entails to dig deeper into communitarian theories. In order to differentiate
my concept of Community from others I will write it with a capital
C in this thesis. The Human Community paradigm I propose is not
a sociological concept but intends to provide a theoretical framework permitting
to rethink Human Rights in a plural though united and praxis oriented way
on the global level. Nevertheless, taking this paradigm seriously will entail
to do further research on communities in a sociological sense. Indeed it
tends towards delegating the management and regulation of their own lives
to the communities most directly concerned, and towards the articulation
of these regulations at the global level .
Part III, Towards a
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights, will lead us to reflect upon
an appropriate myth in which to embed Common Humanities and Human Community,
in order to provide them with a horizon which can endow them with meaning.
As we will see, the Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights (in upper case)
results of the articulation of two dianthropological praxises (in lower case):
the Social Sciences' dianthropological praxis of Human Rights
and the spiritual dianthropological praxis of Human Rights.
Before explaining
dianthropological and exposing the two sorts of dianthropological
praxis, a few more words on praxis. As PANIKKAR notes, after
posing the question whether the notion of Human Rights is a western concept
(1984a : 28) :
It is not a merely 'academic' issue.
Human rights are trampled upon in the East as in the West, in the North as
in the South of our planet. Granting the part of human greed and sheer evil
in this universal transgression, could it not also be that Human Rights are
not observed because in their present form they do not represent a universal
symbol powerful enough to elicit understanding and agreeing?
The challenge will thus be
to emphasis praxis (meaningful practice) of Human Rights, more than
their theoria (their abstract grounding) or their poiesis
(technique). As already noted what is at stake is not the implementation
of a Human Rights system as such, or the efficacy of an a priori
determined Human Rights System.What is at the core of the debate is to rethink
a Human Rights Community permitting a rule of law
on the local and global levels. For the possibility of such a Rule of Law
it is not enough to build on the different cultural theories of Human Rights
to permit the emergence of a universal one. If we want a working
Human Rights Community we must also build on the practices, and
not only on the representations of those who are concerned (and who are not
only the states). Healthy pluralism in the domain of Human Rights thus
necessitates praxis of Human Rights. And on the global level this
praxis must be dianthropological.
In
using the term Dianthropological, I wish to emphasize the three
etymological roots on which it is built : dia : through, anthropos
: man, and logos: discourse or logic. In its first sense
dianthropological praxis wants to designate a praxis stemming
from a journey through the different anthropologies, through the different
logics and discourses of men. It is thus closely related to dialogue
(dia-logos) as we will develop it in Chapter I. The emphasis
on anthropologos and not merely on logos is due to
my intent to bring also the practices of men in the picture next to the logics
and the discourses. The term dianthropological, through the presence
of anthropos in its middle already evokes an association of the
logics, with incarnated human life and thus practice and praxis. Further
as LE ROY (1993b : 235) says, the fundamental requirement of legal anthropology
is always to refer the legal discourses and practices to the underlying
system of thought and to the logic which generate them. In its second
sense dianthropological praxis intents to point to a praxis
originating beyond the domain of the logos of man. It points to a praxis
originating in the most profound spiritual experience in which man has already
gone through the domain of logos, and in which he directly experiences
reality.
We have now outlined the programme of this thesis and have clarified the basic concepts. Before starting to develop them I would only like to make two further remarks. The first is about the positioning of this research in the broader context of globalisation, aspect which I will not develop further in this thesis but which seems primordial to me. The second is about my personal positioning in this research.
We
can find in the discussions on globalisation formulations running parallel
to the ones of Human Rights' universalism or relativism. Indeed globalization
is sometimes thought of as a process of uniformization, or westernization
(some speak of McDonaldization or Cocacolonization
- see : LIE 1997 : 2). And sometimes it is thought of as a process vivifying
the cultural particularisms and thus rather contributing to a dismantling
of a global unity than to its building. If it is trendy nowadays to speak
of a global village, ROULAND (1993a : 214) wonders if this
global village is not an illusion, which under a thin unified
surface of quicker person and information exchange, made possible by modern
technology, hides a conflictual reality where cultures are far from vibrating
in harmony. To him the contemporary situation evokes rather, with the rise
of particularisms, a planetary archipelago than a global
village. Thus globalization is confronted with the same problematics
of universalism and relativism as are Human Rights. But it seems also that
their treatment goes in the same direction as the one advocated by de SOUSA
SANTOS concerning Human Rights. According to LIE (1997 : 3) :
The discussion in the field of international
and intercultural communication has shifted and broadened. It has shifted
in the sense that it is now focusing on issues related to 'global culture',
'local culture', (post)modernity and 'multiculturalism' instead of its previous
concern with modernization, synchronization and cultural imperialism. With
this 'new' discussion, the debate has also shifted from an emphasis on
homogeneity toward an emphasis of differences. (...) With this shift toward
differences and localities there is also an increased interest in the link
between the global and the local and in how the global is perceived in the
local.
We
are thus here also invited to reflect upon ways to articulate the
global and the local, to pay tribute to our common
human condition while acknowledging our differences. To sum up, we are here
also invited to think a healthy pluralism. Furthermore, the Human Rights
debate seems to me not only to run parallel to the globalization debate,
but seems to offer a privileged site (or topos) to reflect upon the
shaping of our global condition. Indeed for ROBERTSON (1996 :
20-21) :
(...) the concept of globalization per
se should be applied to a particular series of developments concerning 'the
concrete structuration of the world as a whole. The term 'structuration'
has been calculatedly chosen. (...) It has to contribute to the understanding
of how the global system has been and continues to be 'made'. It has to be
focused upon the production and reproduction of 'the world' as the most salient
plausibility structure of our time. (...) It is upon this heavily contested
problem of the concrete patterning of the world - including resistance to
globality - that I seek to center the concept and the discourse of
globalization.
It
is my firm belief that Human Rights research in so far as it tries to work
out a paradigm for a global life in peace and dignity for individuals and
their groups of belonging has much to contribute to the structuration
of our global condition. Is it not the role of law to structure life
in society ? For HAURIOU, law is a normative set, if possible codified, which
acknowledges social truces (see KUYU 1995 : 91, LE ROY 1997c : 135). For
BOURDIEU (1986 : 41) codifying is putting in form (shaping) and putting forms.
Law in this light appears clearly as consecrating a social order as well
as the choices of a society. ALLIOT (1983b : 207) expands this view a little
by affirming that law is at the same time struggling and consensus
on the outcomes of the struggling in the domains a society considers as being
vital . Law appears here not only as the putting in form of the consensus,
but also as the reaching of the consensus through conflict. Furthermore ALLIOT's
definition stresses that law is related to that what a society considers
as vital. LEGENDRE's definition of law (in LE ROY 1996a : 8) which characterizes
it as the dogmatic art of knotting together the social, the biological
and the subconscious to assure the reproduction of humanity brings
it even closer to ROBERTSON's production and reproduction of the
world.
In
our Human Rights perspective I would say that the ideal Human Rights
try to represent, Peace, Human Dignity, mutual Respect, are what should be
considered as vital in our global culture. A reflection on Human Rights
Law should permit to realize this ideal by structuring our global
condition, by permitting to produce and reproduce it, in a way that this
ideal can be realized. In this perspective the close link between Human Rights'
research and globalization research appears very clearly. Human Rights research
cannot dwell on a purely legal point of view. It must try to contribute to
work out paradigms permitting to rethink and actively shape the globalization
process in such a way that an embodiment of the Human Rights' Ideal,
in our perspective of the Human Community, in reality, is made possible.
Our particular point of view
(topos of research) is that of a continental European legal theorist
with special commitment to legal anthropology who tries to make a contribution
to the establishing of a Human Community, of a platform for intercultural
dialogue, sharing and exchange. Our perspective on Human Rights is a very
broad one. It keeps in sight the globalisation process. It is also a global
perspective on Human Rights. It does not see them merely in terms of their
efficacy but more broadly as a stake on the national levels to permit a
rule of law, and on the global level to permit a concrete
structuration of the world as a whole in a just and meaningful way.
The just, for me, is linked to the acknowledgement of cultural
diversity. The meaningful is linked to the acknowledgement of
a praxis (meaningful practice) of human rights rather
than to a confinement on their poiesis (technique) or theoria
(abstract grounding of human rights).
The frame is set. Let us now
fill it.
Let us start by telling a little narrative which will illustrate and outline
the stakes of this first part :
There were people playing on all the tables, and often for lots. The night had been long and the smoke which had invaded the gambling joint precluded to see from one table to the other. One would have had to move, and would then have been filled with wonder by the variety. Every table was playing a different game (...) All of a sudden the belote players left their table to observe the bridge table. One of them returned quite quickly having noticed that the bridge players did not know the rules of the game (he was thinking of the rules of belote) and committed many mistakes : optimistic and benevolent, he thought that they would end up learning them and know how to play. Having observed them for a little longer, one of his friends understood that they were not playing belote but some other game : he noted the way in which they ordered the cards and plaid them and rejoined the first one to announce him his discovery. It is then that the third belote player, having guessed that you need to know the rules of bridge in order to understand the game asked the players about them : they handed him a manual, and added that it will not be enough to read it carefully and that he will need a long practice before he could pretend to know bridge.
Thus go human societies. Each one is playing
a particular game which the others struggle to decipher. (ALLIOT 1984
: 269) -2-
Every culture plays its own
legal game - to realise this is already a difficult achievement, but it is
even more difficult to try to understand these different games and even more
difficult to try to articulate them in order to create a new plural game
safeguarding their mutual originality. It will be our attempt in this part
to help the mutual decipherment of cultures' legal games in relation to the
Human Rights problematic in order to gain useful insights permitting us to
construct models which can provide a framework, or a forum, for genuine
intercultural dialogue on an intercultural universality of Human Rights,
permitting us thus to play a global Human Rights game. An
intercultural approach to human rights can only be based on a dialogical
approach, as it presupposes several partners, several points of view. Indeed,
the acknowledgement of pluralism, contained in the intercultural ideal makes
it very important to clearly work out the different places (topoi)
from which the different cultural partners are speaking. This acknowledgement
of the existence of different cultural topoi entails that the mutual
decipherment of the different cultures which constitute the frame of a dialogue
around an intercultural universality of Human Rights itself demands
an epistemological break in favour of intercultural dialogue. This dialogical
approach does thus not only become relevant in the dialogue about human rights
itself but even has to play a crucial part before, in the setting of this
dialogue. Genuine intercultural dialogue on the global level, as well in
its knowledge-seeking as in its consensus-seeking
aspect, needs as a basis an understanding of the other, of the different
localisms, provided for by intercultural dialogical dialogue
(as opposed to a dialectical one). We will thus start by working out the
demands of genuine intercultural dialogical dialogue (Chapter
I). After this (Chapter II) we will try to use the dialogical approach in
order to capture the originality of other cultures' local approaches to
Human Rights and will try to propose a model which can be used
as a forum for intercultural dialogue on a global intercultural approach
to Human Rights rooted in our Common Humanities.
Chapter I : The Requirements
for Genuine Intercultural Dialogue
Nobody can decide a priori what it means
to humanize Man, nor can this totally depend on a single anthropology. It
requires not a methodology but a methodic of its own, which makes its way
in and through the mutual interaction and possible cross-fertilization of
different religions and cultures. A dialogical dialogue is necessary here.
This dialogical dialogue, which differs from a dialectical one, stands on
the assumption that nobody has access to the universal horizon of human
experience, and that only by not postulating the rules of the encounter from
a single side can Man proceed towards a deeper and more universal understanding
of himself and thus come closer to his own realization.
(PANIKKAR 1978 : 90-91)
In
this chapter we will reflect upon the requirements of genuine,
dialogical, intercultural dialogue, the first step towards a
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights. For that purpose we will heavily
draw on PANIKKAR's work in which he has developed some useful tools in his
research on a possible dialogue between religions. We will also draw on some
insights of anthropology which is perhaps the science par excellence
dealing with the relationship of Us and Them
(Eux et Nous, KILANI 1994b : 17 ff), and
especially on DUMONT's concept of encompassing of the contrary
(englobement du contraire) and its consequences. We will start by
expliciting the rhetoric of the dialogue (I). We will
then unveil the perhaps most tricky trap on our way of entering in contact
with the other, the encompassing of the
contrary (II). To try to break out of this trap we will
try to propose the tool of dialogical dialogue (III),
which in its turn will lead us to the choice of diatopical
hermeneutics as the basis of our intercultural Human Rights' dialogue
(IV).
I. The Rhetoric of the
Dialogue
Dialogue, as I
use it in this paper, is not a mere conversation between people. It is rather
a process in which a journey through different logics, or discourses, occurs
in order to go through and beyond them (dia:: through -logos :
discourse) to reach the frame underlying them, their mythos and to
make it explicit, permitting thus true mutual enrichment and exchange (EBERHARD
1996 : 3-4 and 34 ff).
This journey needs
a space where it can take place and I think that this space could adequately
be conceptualized as the in-between (entre-deux) which
van de KERCHOVE and OST develop in their dialectical approach to Law and
which follows from their interdisciplinary epistemological positioning
(van de KERCHOVE, OST 1992 : 51) which parallels our intercultural
epistemological positioning. Let us nevertheless note, as we will develop
further, that our in-between is a dialogical and not a merely
dialectical one. Van de KERCHOVE and OST (1992: 52) explain :
From the moment one refuses the security
of disciplinary particularism and of the totalisation of discourse, one renounces
to the certainties of established knowledge (patchy or total, whichever),
to organize the production of knowledge in an unceasing work of distancing
between existing discourses. It is in this in-between that the shape of our
episteme unveils itself, as it is in the exchange of dialogue that the sense
of our praxis is articulated. -3-
But the creation of an
in-between alone is not sufficient . Furthermore, this
in-between must be potentially fruitful. If the
in-between constitutes the space where the dialogue can take
place, then the rhetoric can be seen as that which shapes this space and
can turn it into either a fruitful, or sterile or even destructive frame
for the dialogue. We will therefore have a closer look now at the rhetoric
of the dialogue.
A,
rather obvious, consequence of the search for a fruitful rhetoric is to try
to achieve a cooperative dialogue (dialogue coopératif) which
means that the partners genuinely seek mutual understanding and enrichment
and a possible consensus. The cooperative dialogue thus excludes
cheating or imposing one's own point of view on the other by taking advantage
of own's dominating position, making thus up alone the questions and the
answers (van de KERCHOVE, OST 1992: 63-64). But if theoretically it appears
easy to judge the cooperative character of a dialogue, in practice
this is far less obvious, as a dialogue can turn out to be
uncooperative not because of a lack of conscious good faith but
rather because unconsciously the partners to the dialogue position themselves
in a way which does not really permit them to engage in a true cooperative
dialogue. TODOROV (1992b : 71) illustrates very well the danger of
the unconscious obstacles to cooperative dialogue which stem
from an unconscious positioning of oneself in the dialogue with his example
of the unconscious universalist :
The relativist does not judge others. The
conscious universalist can condemn them ; but he does so in the light of
an openly assumed morality, which thus can be challenged. The unconscious
universalist is unassailable, as he pretends to be a relativist; but this
does not hinder him to judge others and to impose his ideal upon them. He
has the aggressiveness of the second and the clear conscience of the first
: he is an assimilator in complete innocence, because he is not aware of
the differences of the others. -4-
Thus the unconscious framing
of the dialogue by assuming different unconscious attitudes may constitute
important obstacles to the emergence of a really cooperative
dialogue. PANIKKAR has worked out three attitudes which can frame the rhetoric
of the dialogue and which we should keep in mind if we want to transcend
them in order to be really able to dialogue. We will briefly present these
attitudes by connecting them to our problematic of the building of an
intercultural Human Rights' Dialogue. The three attitudes are
exclusivism, inclusivism and parallelism. Two of them
are already quite familiar to us, and are in a dialectical relationship :
exclusivism which is closely linked to the universalism
discussed above and parallelism which is closely related to the problem
of cultural relativism
Exclusivism
is the attitude where
one is convinced that one's own truth is the only truth and that therefore
there can exist no other truths. The most obvious danger with this attitude
is a lack of tolerance towards different points of views which can lead to
the violent attempt to impose one's own views. A less obvious one is to make
a distinction between objective and subjective truth,
considering of course one's own as the objective one, and accepting the other's
as only some subjective truths (PANIKKAR 1978 : xiv, xv). This
universalistic attitude can thus lead to a justification of relativism,
foreclosing any dialogue : we have discovered the objective truth of human
equality and thus accept that all cultures should live according to their
respective subjective truths (see TODOROV above). We thus can find ourselves
through exclusivism in an attitude of parallelism.
In
the latter attitude we consider that no world view, no culture is perfect
and that we should therefore not try to convert or even interfere with others.
We should only try to deepen the understanding of our own culture which may
permit us to find points of contact with other cultures (PANIKKAR 1978 :
xviii-xix). The problem with this attitude is that it denies the need of
mutual learning and furthermore does not give an adequate solution to our
present global condition in which we cannot dwell solely on our own tradition
but have to participate in our global condition. Exclusivism and
parallelism are the two attitudes we should avoid in order not to
fall in the pitfalls of neither dogmatic universalism nor overvalorisation
of particularisms (LE ROY 1994b : 60).
The third attitude,
inclusivism, does not exclude different truths nor does it consider
them as parallel truths with which one should not mingle :
The inclusivistic attitude will tend
to reinterpret things in such a way as to make them not only palatable but
also assimilable. Whenever facing a plain contradiction, for instance, it
will make the necessary distinctions between different planes so as to be
able to overcome that contradiction. It will tend to become a universalism
of an existential or formal nature rather than of essential content.
(PANIKKAR 1978 : xvi)
Paradoxically such an attitude
makes cooperative dialogue impossible. Indeed it is too
conciliatory, as it sees no conflicts. Furthermore it absorbs
what are perceived by others as conflicts, in its own system,
thus finally appearing as the true system as it encompasses all
the others. We will have to keep this attitude especially in mind when we
will come to propose our intercultural Human Rights' Community
in Part II of this paper, where my attempt will be to show that an intercultural
Human Rights' System cannot any more be a real system, in the
sense of being closed and comprehensive, than a true intercultural dialogue
can be the dialogue of one culture, or an intercultural
monologue (a globalized, uniform discourse on Human Rights). Thus it
has to be conceptualized as a Community.
Having outlined the broad
rhetoric of the dialogue, let us now deal more specifically with one major
bias of present intercultural dialogue, the encompassing of the
contrary, before developing alternatives to break out of it.
II. The Paradigm of
the Encompassing of the Contrary
In
his Essais sur l'individualisme, DUMONT (1991) raises a fundamental
question as to modern ideology : how does it reconcile its diacritical principle
of equality, which stems from our Christian heritage and has completely
crystallized with the Enlightenment, with the hierarchical principle on which
all social organization is based? And what are the consequences of this
construction for our perception of the Others ?
As
to the first question DUMONT's answer is that we perform an encompassing
of the contrary (englobement du contraire). In what does
this consist ? DUMONT gives the following example, taken from the Bible :
God first created Adam, the non differentiated
Man, prototype of the human species. After that, he extracts in a way a being
of a different sex out of this non differentiated being. Here are Adam and
Eve face to face, this time as male and female of the human species. In this
curious operation, Adam has somehow undergone a change of identity, whereas
at the same time appears a being which is both, member of the human species
and nevertheless different from the major representative of that species.
Adam, or in our language Man, is simultaneously two things : the representative
of the human species and the male prototype of this species. On a first level
man and woman are equal, on a second level woman is the opposite or the contrary
of man. These two relationships taken together characterize the hierarchical
relationship, which cannot be better symbolised as by the material encompassing
of the future Eve in the body of the first Adam. This hierarchical relationship
is very generally the relationship between a whole (or a set) and an element
of this whole (or set) : the element is part of the set, is cosubstantial
or identical to it, and at the same time distinguishes itself from it or
is opposed to it. There is no other way to express this in logical terms
than to juxtapose at two different levels those two propositions which taken
together contradict each other. That is what I refer to as 'encompassing
of the contrary'. (Dumont 1991 : 140-141, in a slightly different version
: Dumont 1979 : 39) -5-
Thus the encompassing
of the contrary consists in the fact of explicitly encompassing two
contradictory principles in the same category, thus constructing them as
equal, while implicitly taking one of those principles as the reference in
opposition to which the other is constructed, thus reintroducing a hidden
hierarchy. This permits us to be unconscious universalists
(universalistes inconscients) to use again the words of TODOROV quoted
above. The consequence as to our perception of the Other is
threefold. First, as the approach is monotopical (from one point of observation
- ours) as opposed to a diatopical approach (through different points of
observation - including the internal perspective of the Other)
it leads to a dichotomical construction of the Other. There are
no different Others - there is only We and
They. This, second, leads to an ethnocentrist perception, as
every culture is furthermore only perceived in reference to the dominant
culture, our culture. Changes in our dominant culture will heavily influence
our construction of the Other who is perceived more as our inverted
image, permitting us to delimit our identity, than as an identity of its
own. Thus KILANI (1994b : 19), for example, notes that during the Middle-ages
and the Enlightenment the line between Us and Them
was conceived as a line between culture and nature, man
and monster, Christian and idolaters. Later, in the XIXth
and XXth century, They became integrated in our genealogy, in
the universal history, only to be projected in a historical and social
distance, and to be assimilated to our own past (KILANI 1994b : 20).
LE ROY also notes that all colonialist African studies, like studies on customary
land law (droit foncier coutumier), animist religion etc...,
have been marked by the paradigm of the encompassing of the contrary
thus not being able to account for the originality of the African institutions
but only giving a caricatural and ethnocentric picture of them (LE ROY 1996a
: 3). Last but not least the ideal of equality being closely intertwined
in our modern ideology with that of rationality, uniformity and abstraction,
the explanatory system provided by the encompassing of the contrary
will appear as very objective, rational and scientific and thus universal
and unchallengeable. Let us note here, before moving on, that for LE ROY
(1996a : 3-4) the unitarian way of thinking about legal pluralism (which
is thought in reference to a legal order and where non-state
law is thought as inferior) is another application of the principle
of the encompassing of the contrary.
To
sum up, we can say that the following challenge is facing us : we are invited
to break out of a necessarily reductionist rationalistic construction of
the other marked by the principle of the encompassing of the
contrary. Indeed this construction is characterized by the expansion
of one group of reference and by its transformation into an abstract general
category encompassing all other groups. Although the latter are explicitly
claimed to be equal to the former, they are nevertheless implicitly inferiorized
as they are constructed in reference to the reference group and not according
to their own originality. Thus giving a fair account of the Other
turns out to be impossible. The originality of the other is negated and he
is reduced, in our dichotomical world view, to the inverted image of ourselves.
Genuine intercultural dialogue should permit us to break out of this reductionist
view of the other and should permit us to discover him in his originality.
This should enable genuine mutual exchange and enrichment in order to shed
light on our Common Humanities, or our Universalities. So let
us try to work out the methodology of genuine intercultural dialogue by
presenting dialogical dialogue and by contrasting it to dialectical dialogue
before exposing the diatopical hermeneutics which sustain it.
III. The Dialogical
Approach : Dialogical versus Dialectical Dialogue
It
may be appropriate, before going into further developments, to set out the
frame of the following pages by giving a short definition of dialogical and
dialectical dialogue and by briefly exposing their relationship.
The dialectical dialogue is a dialogue
about objects which, interestingly enough, the English language calls
'subject-matters'. The dialogical dialogue, on the other hand, is a dialogue
among subjects aiming at being a dialogue about subjects. They want to dialogue
not about something, but about themselves : they dialogue themselves. (...)
The dialogical dialogue is not so much about opinions (...) as about those
who have such opinions and eventually not about you, but about me to you.
To dialogue about opinions, doctrines, views, the dialectical dialogue is
indispensable. In the dialogical dialogue the partner is not an object or
a subject merely putting forth some objective thoughts to be discussed, but
a you, a real you and not an it. I must deal with you, and not merely with
your thought. And of course, vice-versa, You yourself are a source of
understanding.
(PANIKKAR 1984c : 209)
Thus, what is at stake in
rethinking our way of conceiving intercultural dialogue and our
construction of the Other, or our mutual construction,
is our concept of universality itself. Breaking out of the paradigm of the
encompassing of the contrary and complementing dialectical dialogue
by dialogical dialogue could be a first step on the way to an intercultural,
and not solely a monocultural universality, of Human Rights. This is so as,
with dialogical dialogue, we do not limit ourselves anymore to speaking of
the object of Human Rights - an object which we take for granted but which
may be problematic for other cultures - but as we use this object to mutually
talk of ourselves, permitting a mutual enrichment and the building of a common
understanding. Reflecting upon dialogical dialogue is thus for
us a way to reflect upon our universalism, upon our way to reach
universality.
To
engage in intercultural universalism we thus seem invited to leave behind
strictly dialectical dialogue which develops in the pure fields of logic
and of Reason, and which can be evaluated by its logic coherence, to make
a step towards dialogical dialogue which does not confine itself to discourse
(logos) but goes as far as to reach the underlying myths
(mythoï) of the discourse. Of course, the dialogical dialogue
itself inhabits a discourse itself underlaid by a myth. But in the case of
dialogical dialogue this is a pluralistic myth, acknowledging the importance
of what the others have to say from their standpoint. It is thus not a
monopolistic discourse excluding different discourses. On the contrary, it
is a discourse explicitly opened to different discourses as it aims at knowing
oneself and the other through the mutual unveiling through dialogue including
our underlying myths. In order to engage into dialogical dialogue we have
to leave behind a monotopical approach of the Other
in favour of a diatopical one. Intercultural dialogue cannot
limit itself to be a journey through our discourse. It must, if it wants
to give a fair picture of all different cultural discourses, be a journey
through all those different cultural discourses. Intercultural dialogue is
thus closely related to the concept of testimony. The partners
to the dialogue are not only partners in a shared discourse but are also
the witnesses of their own cultural discourses. Universality cannot be reached
by pure rational postulation but must be apprehended through concrete live
experiences, of which testimony can be given. It is through the crossing,
the contrasting, the dialogue of these testimonies that an intercultural
universality, a mestizaje of Human Rights may be reached. It seems
that already ROUSSEAU had this intuition on how to reach universality, as
TODOROV (1992b : 34) points out :
The good universalism is thus
above all the one which does not deduce human identity from whatever principle,
but which starts from a profound knowledge of the particular, and advances
by trial and error (...). Furthermore it is the one which rests on at least
two particulars (...) and thus on the establishment of a dialogue between
them; Rousseau destroys here the false evidence held by the ethnocentrist,
the deduction of the universal from the particular. The universal is the
horizon of encounter between two particulars; one may never reach
it, but we nevertheless need to postulate it to render intelligible the existing
particulars. -6-
Before developing with more
depth the diatopical hermeneutics which intercultural universalism
marked by dialogical dialogue requires we will start by reflecting
upon the relationship between testimony and dialogue
which will permit us to clarify the need in the intercultural context to
leave dialectical in favour of dialogical dialogue and will permit us to
grasp the whole relevance of diatopical hermeneutics.
PANIKKAR works out the notion
of dialogical dialogue in relation with the notions of
testimony and witness in Chapter VII : Witness
and Dialogue of his Myth, Faith and Hermeneutics - Cross-Cultural
Studies (1979 : 231 ss). While PANIKKAR (1979 : 232) sees dialogue
(the exchange of views, the encounter of beliefs on equal grounds with
mutual confidence, complete frankness and without ulterior motives)
as a needed basis for the contemporary world he wonders if and how it can
coexist with testimony. Does not the witness refuse dialogue at a certain
point (PANIKKAR 1979 : 233) ? The question arises as :
(...) witness (testimony) is the act
or result of witnessing, of attesting, giving evidence of a conviction one
holds, about which one cares, which one recollects and for which one is
concerned. The witness knows, understands, recollects, is anxious for, concerned
about; he thinks, considers, is preoccupied with what he will manifest to
another in his testimony.
(PANIKKAR 1979 : 238)
The witness thus does not
appear as very ready to abandon his point of view, to change the recollection
of what he has witnessed because of possible arguments developed in the dialogue.
The problem is that testimony and dialogue are on two different levels :
testimony pertains to the realm of lived experience, which is often that
of the unspeakable and is thus of the order of mythos whereas dialogue
places itself on the level of discourse, of rationality, of logos.
The paradox of the intercultural dialogue is that it has to be at the same
time witness (in PANIKKAR's sense) and dialogue to the extent that the different
cultures do not share a common myth which would provide them with a common
frame for discourse. This lack of a shared frame of dialogue in its turn
may make the dialogue itself impossible. It seems thus that our conception
of dialogue has to be revisited in the intercultural context. Our present
conception of dialogue could be defined as dialectical dialogue.
According to the Petit Robert dialectics is the set of tools
used in discussion in order to demonstrate, refute, raise approval. It is
in a more philosophical understanding the art of discussing by way of questions
and answers. It thus appears that dialectical dialogue bears no place for
witness, for mythos, but remains confined to logos. It only
provides one of the necessary tools for intercultural dialogue : the tool
permitting reflexive and critical knowledge on what is discussed. But it
does not provide the equally important tool which would allow integration
in its structure of the testimony of the other cultures, which seems primordial
in genuine intercultural dialogue. On the contrary the irreconcilable aspect
of dialectical dialogue and witness seems to preclude any intercultural dialogue.
Witness seems in the end always bound to close the dialogue as it appeals
to a sphere out of the realm of dialogue (for the above : PANIKKAR 1979 :
240-242). We thus seem condemned to either convert others to our frame of
dialogue, a rational dialogue with no place for value conceptions or world
views, or to resign ourselves to relativism. But there may be another way
proposed by PANIKKAR (1979 : 242-244) : dialogical dialogue :
Now the dialectical dialogue is not
the only, nor even the most important, form of dialogue. Discovering the
capital importance of dialogical dialogue represents an important cultural
mutation in our times. (...) Dialogical dialogue is not the external
reinforcement of a monologue in the belief that 'two heads are better than
one'. (...) Dialogue is, fundamentally, opening myself to another so that
he might speak and reveal my myth that I cannot know by myself because it
is transparent to me, self-evident. (...) Dialogue seeks truth by trusting
the other, just as dialectics pursues truth by trusting the order of things,
the value of reason and weighty arguments. (...) Dialogue does not seek to
be primarily duo-logue, a duet of two logoi, which could still be dialectical;
but a dia-logos, a
piercing of the logos to attain a truth that transcends it. We call this
dialogical dialogue and we add that the relational nature of all
witnessing belongs to this dialogue. (...) If dialogue is more than a dialectical
technique, it cannot dispense with a certain testimony, i.e.,with the
nonapodictic testimony of the other that communicates his experience and
does not merely criticize my views. (...) His testimony says to me (...)
that there are other points of view, other possibilities, that what is
self-evident to me may not be to another. This new sort of dialogue can proceed
only by mutually integrating our testimonies within a larger horizon, a new
myth. What the other bears is not a critique of my ideas but witness to his
own experience, which then enters our dialogue, flows with it and awaits
a new fecundation.
The dialogical dialogue is
thus characterized by its integration of testimony and therefore by its opening
up to praxis. It is also a process in which the partners to the dialogue
undergo a change. By having mutually made a place in themselves for the other,
none of the partners to the dialogue will be able to leave it the way he
entered it. As van de KERCHOVE and OST (1992 : 64) remark :
(...) what one must understand, is that
the dialogical we is not constructed in the unrefined summation
of two monolithical entities : a I and a you constituted
as such in themselves... This I and this you between
which speech circulates are, from the very beginning, divided, split by the
fracture in which the other makes himself heard. There is only a possibility
of dialogue because a place has already been dug in the I which
the voice of the interlocutor can fill. -7-
The dialogical dialogue as
a method to seek knowledge, by integrating the acknowledgement of different
topoi of discourse in the discourse, thus also challenges classical
ways of seeking knowledge, as knowledge is no more merely produced
within a frame but in-between different frames of knowledge.
It thus characterizes all inter-research, may it be intercultural
or interdisciplinary. As COTTERRELL (1996a : 47-48) writes, even though without
explicitly speaking in terms of dialogue :
(...) it may be that the only way in
which knowledge in the human sciences generally (including the study of law)
can escape being limited by the particular configurations of power in the
human activities that make possible each of these specific disciplines (...)
is by confrontation between disciplines, or - to put it another way - the
effective challenging of the mechanisms sustaining the discipline-effect
of these fields. Intellectual confrontations of disciplinary knowledge fields
may be possible to advance knowledge beyond that encompassed by each of them.
It should follow, however, that any such effective confrontation will not
merely add to knowledge but ultimately transform the terms in which knowledge
is sought and conveyed by disrupting the taken-for-granted foundations of
the disciplines involved.
But in order to be able to
play its emancipatory role in knowledge seeking, dialogical dialogue has
to be sustained by an adequate methodology. Indeed the classical methodology
will not do anymore as there is no more abstract all encompassing frame of
reference for the search of dialogical knowledge which emerges
in-between frames and not within a frame. Thus another
factor becomes vital to genuine dialogical dialogue. Witnesses are not
disincarnated selves witnessing some disincarnated truth but they are real
people looking at the world through their specific standpoint. Dialogical
dialogue thus needs to acknowledge those different standpoints, those different
topoi. It renders thus a diatopical approach necessary.
IV. The Diatopical Approach
- Diatopical Hermeneutics
The main issue we have to
deal with here, the core question of diatopical hermeneutics, is how to
understand from the topos of one culture the constructs of another
(PANIKKAR 1984a : 29). This has always been a core question in anthropology
to which the latter has provided the following answer : the anthropologist,
in order to be able to understand another culture, must immerse himself in
it, though keeping some critical distance towards it. He is thus asked to
juggle with the external and the internal points of view
on the cultures, to use a vocabulary familiar to legal theorists (HART 1994
: 88-91, see also : OST, van de KERCHOVE 1987 : 69 ff). It is this decentering,
crystallized in his fieldwork, which permits the anthropologist to gain insights
in another culture. These insights in turn may lead him towards a deeper
understanding of his own culture and hopefully to a deeper understanding
of the Human condition in general in all its diversity which is his ultimate
goal (KILANI 1994a : 47 ff). The anthropologist must thus become the witness
of the culture he is studying - and as a witness he must also be the translator
of this culture to his culture of belonging (KILANI 1994b : 14 ff). To put
it in CASTORIADIS' (1992 : 228) terms :
The ethnologist who has assimilated the
world view of the Bororos to the point that he can only see it in their way,
is no more an ethnologist, he is a Bororo - and Bororos are not ethnologists.
His justification is not to get assimilated to the Bororo, but to explain
to the Parisians, the Londoners, the New Yorkers of 1965 this other humanity
that the Bororo represent. And he can only achieve this through
language, in its most profound sense, in the categorial system of
the Parisians, the Londoners etc . Yet, those languages are not equivalent
codes - precisely because in their structuration, imaginary significations
play a crucial role. -8-
What is therefore needed in
order to engage in intercultural dialogical dialogue is a diatopical approach
sustained by diatopical hermeneutics. The diatopical approach invites us
to make our journey through the different cultural discourses
(dia-logoi) through the different cultural sites from where they emerge
(dia-topoi). The different cultural discourses thus have to be replaced
in their respective underlying myths in order to become mutually intelligible.
It is not enough for a fertile intercultural dialogue on Law to become aware
of the originality of the socio-legal processes and logics of different cultures.
An acknowledgement of their respective legal visions, horizons or universes,
their underlying myths is primordial (VACHON 1990 : 167). And on the level
of these myths we are not on the level of dialectics, of reason, but on the
level of practice, of lived experience. For VACHON (1990 : 169) legal
cultures:
(...) are not only of the order of logos
but of the order of mythos, which means of the order of ultimate differences.
And ultimate differences are not dialectical (which does not mean that they
are non-dialectical or anti-dialectical). -9-
We
are thus again invited to think in a fundamentally plural way, acknowledging
that there may be fundamentally different choices that Men have made to think
about their lives and to organize them. Our goal can, in this perspective,
no longer be to try to work out an all-comprehensive universal explanatory
model, reducing this diversity to an artificial unity. It must rather be
to find ways to make our different myths mutually intelligible thus permitting
their interfecundation, their articulation, their mestizaje. We thus
seem invited to engage in diatopical hermeneutics which means according to
PANIKKAR (1984a : 29) that :
We must dig down to where a homogeneous
soil or a similar problematic appears : we must search out the homeomorphic
equivalent - to the concept of Human Rights in this case. 'Homeomorphism
is not the same as analogy; it represents a peculiar functional equivalence
discovered through a topological transformation'. It is 'a kind of existential
functional analogy.'
Before engaging now, as the
requirements and the stakes are clarified, in diatopical hermeneutics and
an intercultural dialogical dialogue on Human Rights, let us recall a last
primordial requirement of both diatopical hermeneutics and dialogical dialogue
: this whole approach can only make sense if we never forget our own topos
of speech. Our utterances cannot encompass the whole of a problematic and
cannot represent all points of views. They can only be an invitation to further
dialogue, to further knowledge seeking in-between. Also, the
relevance and coherence of our utterances can, as there is no more general
universal frame of research, only be evaluated by taking into account their
topos of origin. The acknowledgement of our topos of research must thus be
at the core of any pluralist research in in-betweens. As BAUER
(1996: 199-200) writes :
Standpoints and perspectives necessarily
become the focus of attention, as soon as the concept of the universal observer
is dismissed or limited. With the understanding of the relevance of the choice
of the point of reference or of observation, appears also the hollow character
of relativity clamour in the plurality discussion. As Mandelbrot (...) shows,
the measure depends on the standpoint of observation even in the physical
mesofield, which is the embodiment of objectivity and stability (...) The
choice of the measuring unit (of the standpoint) turns into a question of
adequacy in relation to the pursued goals and interests. Nevertheless, once
the point of observation is chosen and defined, the measurement (...) becomes
a question of accuracy of measurement, as it has always been. The same is
true in the transition between incommensurable paradigms. They can only be
argumented in their concrete context. Therefore the appropriateness of the
chosen standpoint (of the meta-discourse) as well as the accuracy - from
the chosen perspective - of the observations that have been carried out must
be proven. -10-
Chapter II : Crystallizing and Modelling our Common Humanities
We have become aware in Chapter I that our outlook on the world and on Law
is not self evident. It is underpinned by a myth which can only be rendered
explicit through dialogue with the other cultures and the acknowledgement
of their underlying myths. Law as such is thus not a universal
fact, as SINHA (1995a : 31 ff) demonstrates in his thesis of
non-universality of law. For SINHA, Law cannot be equated
to social organization but is only one particular form of it, developed by
western civilization and largely ignored by other civilizations like China,
India, Japan or Africa (SINHA 1995a : 32). Though agreeing with him on the
principle, we will nevertheless use in this Chapter the term Law
while speaking of other legal cultures. But we will use it in
the sense of a broader working definition than it is usually used in western
legal science. We will not call Law state law or a set or system of rules
or norms, but more generally the legal phenomenon
(phénomène juridique) as ALLIOT (1983b : 209-210) defines
it, and which, he argues, can be found in every society :
Its generality stems from the fact that it is in the nature of man and of society. Being, is struggling, individually or collectively. But no one can fight on one front of his domain as long as he is not assured of peace on all its other borders. And the fighting of its members is not without danger for the group. In the domains a society considers as vital - and thereupon every society has its own conception- its existence is only possible insofar as its members control, to the extent they can, these struggles or at least the practices that result from them. Living in society, is therefore not only struggling, it is also agreeing on the legitimacy or the illegitimacy of these practices and on the consequences that shall be given to them. Social life calls for consensus. The phenomenon is general because it is linked to the nature of the individual (struggle) and to the requirements of life in society (consensus) . (...)
The law of a society is thus ordered around the limits of the spheres of action of all the domains it considers as vital : it is at the same time consensus on these limits and practices, aimed at, or succeeding in, confirming or displacing them.
Thus defined, law is not linked by its nature
to the existence of a state, nor to the formulation of rules, nor to the
recognition of its rationality. -11-
ALLIOT's definition places
itself on the ground of homeomorphic equivalences and thus permits us to
engage in dialogical intercultural dialogue as outlined in Chapter I. As
he points out himself :
Whoever wants to understand the form and
the meaning of the legal institutions of a society has great interest not
to relate them to the institutions of his own society - the connection would
be superficial - but to the universe of the society in which he observes
them. (ALLIOT 1983b : 215) -12-
We
will therefore start by presenting ALLIOT's theory on legal archetypes, logics
and their relationship which can in his opinion permit the elaboration of
models necessary to the constitution of a science of Law (I). We will
then try to crystallize our different legal humanities by giving an overlook
on a few major traditions (II). Finally we will try to propose models
of these different humanities in order to propose a common meeting place
which could constitute a platform for a dialogical intercultural dialogue
on Human Rights (III).
I. Thinking God - Thinking Law -
Legal archetypes and
logics
It
will not be necessary to dwell very extensively here on ALLIOT's theory of
legal archetypes and logics as we have already a good preunderstanding of
it through our previous dealing with the requirements of intercultural dialogue
and as we will see it working in practice while presenting our world's major
legal traditions. We will therefore at this place only try to outline his
theory and to shed some light on it, in a way to avoid any possible
misconceptions that could arise from a relativistic and frozen perception
of Law that one might get of ALLIOT's theory and model at first sight.
In short, ALLIOT's theory can be summed up, as he himself used to do in front of his students in the following phrase : Thinking God is thinking Law. In this phrase, God must be understood as a metaphor for the ultimate causality principle which we see as organizing the world we live in. Thus, in order to be able to understand other cultures' law, we must locate it in the world, the universe from which it originates - and cannot content ourselves to compare it to our own institutions. Therefore we have to understand the other cultures' universes. These universes are not only the visible universes in which men live, made up by different material, geographical, economical etc... conditions but are primarily their invisible universes in which men make sense out of their daily experience. It is the latter which give coherence and meaning to the former : the visible can only be understood in reference to the invisible, not only as a whole but also in its particular manifestations (ALLIOT 1983b : 215). As we have noted above, different cultures can be understood as different human universes. They have different basic assumptions, which do not bear a mutual dialectical relation as VACHON noted (see above : p 21), but are fundamentally different as they share in different myths. They thus invite us to a journey to their core - and thus to a diatopical approach permitting us to understand them from inside, to reveal their underlying myth, their way of thinking of God and of Law.
It
may be worthy to note that, if ways of conceiving the universe, God (as defined
above) and Law show undeniable parallels in our world's societies, this does
not mean that one conception has priority over the others and entirely determines
them. It is neither our way of organizing our society which will give emergence
to a certain religion or philosophy, nor our religion or philosophy which
will induce a certain kind of Law. It is rather the underlying archetype
of conceiving the universe as a whole that will be manifested in a coherent
manner in the different realms and activities of life including religion,
philosophy or Law (ROULAND 1988 : 401, 1995a : 12). Furthermore, it should
not be forgotten that these different archetypes are not a reality
out there, a rigid structure imposing itself on the different societies
as we would conceive of a legal system which would impose itself within a
state. They are just models of ways people live their lives and conceive
it. We should recall here what RÉGNIER (1971 : 18-19) says on models
in order to know what to expect of ALLIOT's model. Thus we will be able to
understand clearly its link to the dialogical and intercultural perspective
we have chosen on Law to enable us to reflect upon an intercultural universality
of Human Rights :
The model constitutes a representation
of a phenomenon which is both simplified and global. Indeed one does not
make a model in order to represent all the properties of a phenomenon, all
the relations that beings have among themselves, all the aspects of the concrete
fact. On the contrary, one envisages the phenomenon from a certain point
of view (...) One makes an abstraction of certain aspects of the concrete,
which simplifies. Further the selected aspects are not arbitrary; they are
chosen from a certain point of view, but all that are relevant to this point
of view must be chosen, which renders global the representation provided
by the model. -13-
ALLIOT's model is thus a global,
but simplified, model of Law. He proposes it as a contribution to the elaboration
of a non-ethnocentric science of Law (ALLIOT 1983b : 208). It is relevant
for us to the extent that it permits genuine intercultural reflection and
dialogue on Human Rights, as we have outlined above. This does not exclude
that for other purposes other models may be more appropriate.
ALLIOT (see ROULAND 1988 :
401-405, 1995a : 7-12) distinguishes three main different legal myths which
he calls archetypes and to which correspond different logics.
We will develop these archetypes and logics on the following pages. Here
I will only give a short overlook which will be clarified by the subsequent
developments and which is only intended to provide us with a general orientation
as to where we are going.
The first one is the archetype
of identification, exemplified by ancient China; it is complemented
by a logic of self-improvement through the respect of rites and of
complementarity of opposites. The second is the archetype of
differentiation exemplified by ancient Egypt and animist Africa;
it is complemented by an autocentered logic which renders those
societies responsible for themselves and which also reasons in terms of
complementarity of opposites. The third is the archetype of submission
exemplified by Islamic and Western civilization; it is complemented by a
logic of deresponsibilization of society itself in favour of an exterior
entity and which thinks in terms of opposites excluding each other.
Concerning the logics and their relationship to the archetypes, ALLIOT makes
three important remarks. First of all he reminds that, if one often speaks
of different rationalities for people belonging to different cultures (the
rationality of the Buddhist or of the Christian etc ...), there is only one
reason (raison) which all human beings share. Nevertheless
there are different societal logics stemming from different necessities,
choices and postulates which ALLIOT mainly divides according to the criteria
of the exercise, or the delegation by the society of the exercise, of the
responsibility for its future. Secondly he observes that similar logics are
at work in societies having opposite archetypes. Finally he notes that different
logics co-exist in one society, corresponding to different situations and
contributing thus to the constitution of the legal model of that society
(ALLIOT 1983b: 227).
Having now all the tools to
understand the following models, let us try to crystallize the different
legal archetypes and logics of our Common Humanities.
II. Crystallizing our
Common Humanities
We
will present one after the other the archetypes of identification,
where social order is sought to be conformed to the cosmic order,
differentiation, where order is seen as the harmonious interplay
of differentiated forces, and submission, where order is seen
as the submission of society to a superior order. After this, we will add
the Indian archetype which is a mixture of the three precedent ones.
1.
Identification
The archetype of identification
and its logic are best exemplified by the Chinese and especially by the Confucian
thought which though very ancient still influences, often in an indirect
manner, the daily life of the Chinese and their conception of society (LE
ROY 1992b : 149). Confucian thought is underlaid by an archetype founded
on the principle of duality and complementarity, and by the idea of dynamic
harmony (LE ROY 1995a : 15).This archetype is best symbolised by the famous
symbol of the Tao, the T'ai-chi T'u, or Diagram of the
Supreme Ultimate which shows the dynamic intertwinement and harmony
of the yin and the yang, the two fundamental principles standing
for the male and the female, the day and the night, the weak and the strong
... (CAPRA 1992 : 119). This representation of the ultimate, of the
Tao, immediately strikes us by its eminently dynamic nature, which
becomes very evident in its English translation as the Way. As
CAPRA says (1992 : 116-117) :
The Chinese, like the Indians, believed
that there is an ultimate reality which underlies and unifies the multiple
things and events we observe (...) They called this reality the Tao, which
originally meant 'the Way'. It is the way, or process, of the universe, the
order of nature. (...)
It is characterized
by its intrinsically dynamic quality which, in the Chinese view,
is the essence of the universe. The Tao is the cosmic process in which all
things are involved; the world is seen as a continuous flow and
change.
For the Chinese there is thus
no infinite God who has created and who governs a finite world. The world
is infinite in number and time. There are a plurality of worlds which appear
and disappear endlessly during huge cosmic periods which cannot be apprehended
by the human mind. Infinite and finite are as closely intertwined as are
the yin and the yang of which they are an expression. Therefore,
in its dynamism, the world is not limited by any law imposed on it from the
exterior. It just regulates itself spontaneously by following its way. The
individual has to do the same, in order to conform the human to the cosmic
order (ALLIOT 1983b : 216, LE ROY 1992b : 150). Man must spontaneously follow
his way which then coincides with the Way, the Tao. He thus becomes
part of the cosmic harmony. This world view is well illustrated in one of
LAO-TZEU's (1979 : 69) verses:
A something was, not defined but fulfilled
Born before Heaven-and-Earth
Without speech as without boundary
Independent immutable
Playing itself everywhere without tiredness
In sum the Mother of the world
Not knowing her name I call her Way
(...)
(...) Man is one of the four Great of the world
Man follows the ways of the Earth
The Earth follows the ways of Heaven
Heaven follows the ways of the Way
And the Way follows its own
ways. -14-
Confucius' philosophy is based
on this idea of the Way, of the Tao. It is a reaction against the
loss of the Tao, of the divine mandate by the governments of his time
(he lived from 551 B.C. to 479 B.C.). In Confucian thought the term
Tao takes on a slightly different meaning from the original Taoist
one. It is not merely used to refer to the ultimate reality but it is also
used as the Tao of man, or the Tao of Human Society. In this
use Tao is understood as the right way of life in a moral sense, which
depends on its conformity to the cosmic order (CAPRA 1992 : 117, CONFUCIUS
1981 : 17). Thus it is not a set of rules, or law as we conceive it, which
has to play a central part in social organization. The Confucian ideal is
an ideal of self-improvement possible through education and of self-discipline
which should be guided by the observance of the rites (li). It is
through education and personal improvement that one becomes a full
human being :
(...) one must earn rights by achieving
some minimal level of personhood, of humanity. That is, entitlement to the
privileges and benefits offered by society requires demonstration of credentials
as a participating member of society. As David Hall and Roger Ames remark
: A person is not entitled to political participation because he is born
into an exclusive jen (human being) class. Rather, he becomes jen as a
consequence of that personal cultivation and socialization that renders him
particular. Being a person is something one does, not something one is; it
is an achievement rather than a given.
(PEERENBOOM 1993 : 305)
This focus on personal improvement
is also reflected in the requirement for the sovereign to have become a
jun-zi, a man tending to the realisation of the sovereign good,
ren (CONFUCIUS 1981 : 19-20). He should be a model to his subjects
and is seen as the great educator. Instead of governing by force he should
govern by virtue mediated by rites (CONFUCIUS 1981 : 22 ff). CONFUCIUS (1981
: 33) says :
Govern through the force of laws, maintain
order through the use of punishments, the people will just obey, without
feeling the slightest shame. Rule through Virtue, harmonize through rites,
the people not only will know shame, but on its own will tend towards the
Good. -15-
Li (the set of rites) is the keystone of social
organization. It provides, as LE ROY points out, the mould in which human
action is shaped and becomes meaningful. It determines the models of behaviour
and conduct of individuals and groups, the groups (families, ethnic groups,
professional corporations) enjoying an auto regulation parallel to the personal
auto discipline (LE ROY 1995a : 16, 1997a : 6). Concerning Li PEERENBOOM
(1993 : 309) writes :
Of central importance to the historically
rich Confucian world view and its non-rights based method of conflict resolution
are the li. The li - conventionally translated as rites - may be understood
more broadly to include the full range of social customs, ethical norms,
and political principles embodied in the complex relations, organizations,
and institutions of society. (...) the li are important not merely as the
amassed wisdom of the ages, but also because they are the communally-owned
repository of shared meaning and value on which people can draw in times
of conflict. (...) By tapping the areas of commonality, one may be able to
find the ground upon which to build consensus, to forge new harmony.
Fa (law), or the administrative intervention of
the mandarinate thus only had a limited role to play in the organization
of the Chinese society and was only reserved to those who either did not
respect the rites, the impious, or did not know them, the strangers (LE ROY
1995a : 16). Let us note that through li Confucian thought thus doubly
recognizes legal pluralism by recognizing fa next to li, and
by respecting the different li of the different social groupings.
Li constituted the basis for government action until
1912, the use of fa remaining exceptional, and it does not seem that
the first modernization of the Kuomintang, nor the socialist period have
fundamentally changed those conceptions. The duties of the individuals remain
still as important as their rights, the interest of the collectivity still
prevails over the interest of the individual - and the concepts of Rule
of Law (or Etat de Droit) remain problematic in a society
where social regulation is much more centered around the notions of rites
and self-regulation than around the concept of law (LE ROY 1995a : 16) and
where substantive justice tends to take precedence over formal justice
(PEERENBOOM 1993 : 310). It seems thus that even today in order to go towards
a working Human Rights system within the Chinese sphere one will
not be able to elude the question as to a Chinese theory of Rights, as PEERENBOOM
(1993 : 314 ff) argues, which will have to have its roots in the Confucian
heritage. This acknowledgement of the Confucian world view will also be important
for the possibility of dialogue on Human Rights between cultures aimed at
talking to, rather than past, each other.
Before finishing with the
archetype of identification we should note that although we have illustrated
it with the example of China, it also has widespread influence in the rest
of Asia which shares the Confucian defiance towards law. In Japan
for example giri-ninjô, the set of rules of behaviour established
by tradition for the various types of human relationships, play a role analogous
to that of li in China. The notion of duty is also very strong : one
owes respect to the elders, to the authorities and to order in general. Disputes
are mainly settled according to the will of the parties. Compromise is emphasized
over the recourse to one's rights - and in general recourse to law is perceived
as a failure. As Takeyoshi KAWASHIMA writes : Law in Japan is like
an heirloom samurai sword : it is to be treasured but not used (quoted
in : HALEY 1982 : 299).
Let us now move on to the
archetype of differentiation.
2.
Differentiation
ALLIOT illustrates this archetype
with the help of ancient Egypt and the African animist traditions (1983b
: 219-222). We will leave aside ancient Egypt and focus more especially on
the African animist traditions which share their archetype with other animist
societies spread over the whole globe (LE ROY : 1995a : 18). As we will see,
this archetype shares the valorisation of auto regulation and complementarity
of the opposites that we have met in the Confucian archetype. It is also
characterized by a dynamic outlook on reality. Nevertheless, it differentiates
itself from the Confucian archetype by its fundamentally plural and not only
dual character. Life in society is in those animist societies often only
seen as possible through its ternary structuration through which a complementary
collaboration of the different social, moral or political energetic forces
becomes possible, thus allowing their dynamic harmony (LE ROY 1995a : 19).
The world view of the animist
societies is founded on the idea that the universe is built on the basis
of a circulation of energies and that its vital principle, the anima,
itself is regulated by this movement of energies. This movement is headed
towards the harmony and the equilibrium of the whole by an unceasing search
for interdependence and complementarity. This leads to the conception of
an invisible and visible universe conceived on the basis of multiple, specialized
and interdependent instances (LE ROY 1995a : 19). We will start by illustrating
the plural and complementary aspect of animist thought before presenting
the originality of its correlated dynamic approach to life which privileges
function over being. We will then finish the presentation by exposing
custom (coutume) which is the main instrument of social
regulation in animist communitarian social life.
In
the cosmologies of African animist societies there is no God Creator.The
world emerges progressively from chaos, which already contained in an indistinct
way all the potential future. First emerges a primordial god, followed by
other gods and powers which often manifest as complementary couples and finally
Man. It is thus, unlike as in our myth of creation, the multiple, the unstable
and the unorganized which constitute the foundation of the world.
The world creates itself at each instant and Man plays an important part
in this process by contributing to the preservation of the universe's harmony.
The unity of society is thus not perceived as the result of the obedience
to a uniform, superior order but as the affirmation of distinct groups, who
mutually need each other and are therefore seen as complementary and united.
Differences being conceived as the basis of unity, western uniformizing
legislation, because it erases them, is often perceived as a threat to it.
Furthermore as general immutable external rules are rejected Men are seen
as themselves responsible for their future - which they create every day
anew through custom (coutume) valorising conciliation and a unanimist
spirit (ALLIOT 1983b : 219-222, 1984 : 283 ff, 1980b : 469 ff).
Before having a closer look
at custom and in order to permit us to grasp its profound originality
and not to reduce it to some non-written, imperfect law, we shall
say a few words, after those on differences and their complementarity, on
the primate of function in animist thought.
As
we have already noted, at the core of animist thought we find the dynamic
structure of the universe. Movement is not the result of an exterior constraint,
but flows from the internal dynamism of the universe. This view is reflected
in animist law which privileges becoming over being, a functional over an
institutional approach. ALLIOT (1984 : 274) notes that the original African
Laws do not know beings destined to accomplish functions : it is function
which determines beings. And he adds that in this point of view the African
logic goes much further than Durkheimian or Malinowskian functionalism, which
presuppose beings preexisting to functions, as they see the organs of the
society deemed to satisfy the needs of the beings constituting it. In our
Western view, rather than the beings themselves, functions determine social
spaces or fields (ex : the political or legal field) in which beings evolve
(the beings can be individuals, or companies, or the state etc...). In the
African view, on the contrary persons, lineages, the state or even goods
are themselves defined by their functions. It is not possible to identify
them as a determined type of being - identities are thus multiple and changing
(ALLIOT 1984 : 276). ALLIOT (1984 : 274-275) gives the following example
as to individuals :
At the image of God, absolute function beyond being, the universe is not a set of beings but a set of functions which determine beings.
This is the case with family or social functions which determine the status of individuals. In Europe the individual is a person from birth to death, with a right to invariable rights for each and identical for all. The notion of legal personality does not belong to the original African Laws. There one finds the notion of status and of status determined by the functions one accomplishes : the individual status is all the more important as one gets older, as one gets married (and for a man having several wives), as one gets children, as one gets at the head of a lineage, etc . (...)
Being is so unstable that one easily passes from
one form to another. -16-
The view of man reflects this
general attitude. For the Wolof (a community living in Senegal), the
human being is constituted by three elements : the yaram (or physical
envelope), the rab (the ancestral spirit inhabiting the body of the
new born child) and the fit, the vital energy which can increase and
decrease according to social behaviour and ritual practices. The human being
can only access legal life (vie juridique) through his inscription
in a community and by exerting his responsibility in the community or, later,
in order to represent it - children are, for example, at their birth inscribed
in three communities which they will never leave : their family of procreation,
their lineage, and their age group - but it is only little by little, and
only after their initiation that they become complete members of the legal
community (LE ROY 1995a : 19-20). This view reminds us of the
Confucian view exposed above and is in complete contradiction with our Western
conception of an abstract individual.
Custom (la coutume)
crystallizes this original outlook on life in the legal field. It would be
a big mistake, as we can feel through what we already know of animist thought,
to conceive of it as a set of non written eternal rules which would furthermore
be autonomous from the other social spaces, as we conceive them, like religion
or morals. As ALLIOT (1984 : 277) writes :
Custom (la coutume) is not a being,
like a set of laws would be : it is the way to be, to speak, to act, permitting
everyone to contribute at his best to the preservation of the cohesion of
the group (...) Furthermore, this same function of cohesion often entails
avoidance of the invocation of custom : the ideal is not to let conflicts
lead to an open confrontation. And if the latter cannot be avoided, a solution
is sought, not so much by relying on previously fixed rules, but in conformity,
to what is perceived case by case, as being in the interest of the group.
The solution which crystallizes in the womb of the village is
preferred to the application of law. -17-
To
sum up one could say that custom, as the way of saying
the ways of doing of the ancestors (LE ROY 1995a : 19) is rather a
form than a normative content. This form is malleable and lays emphasis on
the models of conduct and behaviour (modèles de conduite
et de comportement) which constitute the reference for the evaluation
of social behaviour. It furthermore permits to attain the ideal of solving
conflicts inside the group in which they arose (cii bir u keur, in
the womb of the family, as the Wolof from Senegal say), thus emphasising
the responsibility of the group for its own future (LE ROY 1995a: 19).
This communitarian approach
is thus in opposition to our archetype of submission which emphasises
deresponsibilisation in favour of an exterior authority :
We are at the antipodes of the system in which, at the image of a God of whom everything depends in a continuous creation of every instant, the rights of the ones and the others are only maintained through the grace of the one who is the parent of all those rights, the State. The law of the communities does not need a power who deems it worthy to maintain them. It is the necessary consequence of their structure. (ALLIOT 1980a : 158)
-18-
Let us now move to the archetype
of submission.
3.
Submission
This archetype is shared by
the cultures of the religions of the Book. We will illustrate it through
the Western world view and the world view of Islam. It immediately strikes
us by its difference to the two archetypes presented above : first, the world
is created by a power exterior to it. Being prevails over becoming; differences
are not seen as complementary in their mutual interplay, but are seen as
excluding each other; and the world does not get its coherence through the
mutual attraction of its elements but by laws which are imposed on it from
the outside. Second, the responsibility of the society for its life and thus
for its future gets decentered. It does not lie in the womb of society. Society
does not continuously recreate its life at each instant but its management
is transferred to an exterior authority. In the case of the modern state,
it is the latter which becomes the responsible authority - other communities
are pushed to the background insofar as they constitute an obstacle to the
control by the state of its citizens, seen as autonomous and equal individuals
(ROULAND 1988 : 404-405). ALLIOT characterizes the archetype of submission
and its correlated logic of deresponsibilization as follows :
(...) for the Christian West God is the
One who is, before being the One who creates : he Is since all eternity,
he could have not created, or created differently. In him Being takes precedence
over action. At his image, the West affirms precedence of being over function.
(...) Also, it is not indifferent that for the Christian West the unique
God is radically exterior to its creation, that he is recreating it at each
moment and that he governs it in a sovereign way through the uniform constraint
of his laws and decrees. (ALLIOT 1984 : 271) -19-
We
should note that modern legal thought, especially the continental European
one, giving a central place to the state and to state law is only a rationalized
version of this archetype. ALLIOT makes a comparison of this vision with
the conception of Law and State of French jurisprudence, which may be one
of the most striking examples for the archetype of submission. In this conception
society can only be conceived as a set of persons enjoying the same plenitude
of legal being, whatever their functions or responsibilities. The State,
secularized avatar of God, can only be conceived as unique and all-mighty,
centralised and exterior to its citizens. It is the State which permits them
to live by granting them their legal being and the rights through which they
can act. Furthermore it controls them through uniform laws and decrees. There
is no Law outside the state and its uniform laws (ALLIOT 1984 : 271). In
addition to the reduction of diversity to homogeneity, this archetype bears
a logic of deresponsibilisation :
Society is then decentered : it projects
its center out of itself; above itself. The relationships between its members
change completely. They are not anymore centered on the research at each
moment of the just attitude between them. The just attitude is to conform
to the system of rules established by the power, or if they are not satisfactory,
to demand a new law, a new regulation. (ALLIOT 1983b : 234) -20-
Through rationalization this
conception has become universal in our Western minds. State and state law
are seen as rational and thus as universal and as the best ways of organizing
life in society. Through colonialism we have exported our universal
model and have proposed (and imposed) it as The model for societal
organisation. If I speak of The model, although there are different
forms of State, I do so because this model has a few characteristics that
all the diverse manifestations of the modern state share : it is constructed
with a direct reference to Reason which gives it a pretension to universality.
It involves autonomy of the political space and creation of a public sphere
distinct from civil society (BADIE 1995a : 70 ff). Further it is characterized
by the principle of territoriality which takes precedence over communitarian
allegiances (BADIE 1995a : 82 ff) and by its unification through law (BADIE
1995a : 99 ff). By now this model of State has been adopted all over the
world - not without creating lots of troubles to the cultures who adopted
it without sharing our archetype and the conditions in which our modern state
law emerged (BADIE 1995a : 69 ff). It is only recently that the universality
of our model has started to be challenged in the continental European legal
culture, that the generality, the rationality, the stateboundness of our
law have started to be questioned in order to move towards a
postmodern conception of law recognizing relativism, pluralism
and pragmatism (ARNAUD 1990 : 81). It is also fairly recent that more and
more voices from other cultures raise to claim the originality of their own
archetypes and logics. And this thesis touches right upon the core of this
problematic of the western societal archetype which has claimed its universality
and is now being challenged, obliging us to rethink the scope of our possible
contribution to World Law, and to rethink the notions of
universality.
As I am writing this thesis from the point of view of a legal theorist who has been predominantly trained in the continental European tradition, it may be useful to stress the different treatment of the relationship between State and Law in British and Anglosaxon common law theory. The latter may to some extent be closer to Islamic legal thought, which we will expose below, than to the continental European one as present, for example, in France or in Germany.
First the Anglo-Saxon tradition
seems to see law more as a matter of principles than as a matter of rules.
COTTERRELL (1989 : 22-23) asks and remarks :
But how far is this common law an affair
of rules ? Here, as
in many other inquiries about classical common law thought it is important
to avoid imposing on the common law tradition modern interpretations reflecting
views about law derived from wholly different theoretical premises (...).
To write of common law as a system of rules (...) is to impose just such
an alien conception on it. (...) The idea of common law as principles
of law seems more appropriate for capturing (its) shifting, dynamic character,
if only because principles suggest flexible guidelines for legal decision-making
rather than rules which control.
Second, in common law theory
law seems to find its source rather in the community than in the state.
It is the product of the community grounded in its history,
as interpreted and applied by the judges (COTTERRELL 1989 : 25). Further
COTTERRELL (1989 : 32-33) writes :
The idea of judicial authority rooted
in community remains perhaps the strongest, most vibrant, contribution of
common law thought. Its explanations of political law-making through legislation
remain perhaps its weakest, flimsiest elements.
These few words on common
law thought provide us with a bridge to enter Islamic legal thought. I strongly
believe, although I cannot go into an extensive argument here, that it would
be very beneficial for continental lawyers to learn more about common law
thought in a perspective of intercultural legal research. Despite the intrinsic
interest of the endeavour this may permit continental lawyers to broaden
their perspective on law while still remaining in the frame of
Western culture. This may then also permit us to approach Law
of other cultures more openly. It may permit us to see it not as something
very far away, as something completely irreconcilable with our
own thought. It may permit us to build up a healthier relationship to
acknowledging differences. Indeed, we will already have made the experience
that great differences even exist in what we consider as belonging to our
own Western culture. Therefore it will appear that differences cannot be
reduced to a necessity of cultural distance, and of a cultural
distance furthermore often constructed as being unbridgeable. This
broadening of perspective will rather permit us to approach law in a more
subtle way, rendering more of its complexity. But let us now move to Islam.
Islam although sharing the
archetype of submission, gives it a different interpretation than the one
we have already exposed above for the Christian, Western tradition.
The most obvious difference to the Western interpretation is its sacred
character. In Islam no secularisation of Law occurred like in Western culture.
There is thus a radical opposition between Western and Muslim law. In the
continental European view law has its source in the State. It thus originates
in a secular power. In common law it has its source in community, and thus
also in a secular and not a divine reality. In Islam, on the contrary, the
ultimate source of law is God. There can be no man made law. Koranic law,
sharia, imposes itself on the worldly powers - it legitimizes or condemns
them. The role of the Muslim state should be to assure the respect of divine
law, thus permitting its citizens to acquire the dignity which is based on
precisely this respect. In Islam, Law transcends Man. It cannot be apprehended
in its totality - it is not possible to conceive of a complete, even though
modifiable, edifice of law as we do for instance in continental European
legal thought. It always has to be rediscovered through a constant effort
which inevitably leads to divergences. These divergences are accepted, and
Islamic law can be characterized by its sense of morality, interdependence
and solidarity (ALLIOT 1983b : 223-224). In this sense, the archetype of
submission as interpreted by Islam is closer to the two first archetypes
described above than to its Western counterpart. For LE ROY (1995a : 17)
Islam locates itself between the unitarianism of modern Western cultures
and the dual structure of Confucian thought. Though affirming the principle
of unity, it admits a second referent which, however, is not in a complementary
but in a hierarchical relation to the first. Thus if there is only one God,
Mahomet is his prophet. If there is only one community of believers, the
umma, its plurality, in the forms of different rites or schools or
brotherhoods (confréries) which interpret the Koranic message
in their way, is accepted. Parallel to the Qoran and the
Sharia, reasoning of the lawyers and local customs are seen as sources
of law . The Fiqh, or science of Law, itself is not uniform but
encompasses a science of proofs (usul al-fiqh) and theology (usul
ad-din). The complex interplay between those two poles permits various
interpretations of law which can either lean rather towards reason, or towards
religious faith, through ijtihad.
The distinction between law and its sources is carefully maintained in Islamic jurisprudence. This distinction assumes that Holy Law, as the aggregate of divinely-ordained rules, is not entirely self-evident from the sacred texts. If it were, the sacred texts would not be the sources of law, but rather the Law itself (...) In fact, the sacred texts do not, as a rule, state the Law in a strictly legal sense, in the sense that a code or similar instrument states law. They do, however, contain the Law. Because the Law is buried, as it were, within the (legally) imprecise and sometimes ambiguous language of the sacred texts, it is said to be extracted from the texts; and it is for this reason that the texts are to be considered sources of the Law rather than the Law itself.
The process of extracting or deriving (...)
legal rules from the sources of Law is termed, with reference to its character
as a human activity,
ijtihad. Ijtihad
literally means endeavour or self-exertion.
(WEISS 1978 : 273-274)
HALLAQ (1984 : 287) defines
ijtihad as the maximum effort expended by the jurist to master
and apply the principles and rules of usul al-fiqh (legal theory)
for the purpose of discovering God's law.
It
would thus seem that through ijtihad, in its interplay between the
rights of God (huquq al-llah) and the rights of Man (Adam) (huquq
Adam), a counterpart to the Western concept of Human Rights, could emerge
backed by ijma, or consensus, of the community, and qiyas,
reasoning per analogy, whereas Western Human Rights could never be transposed
as such to Islam which only recognizes the Law of God. However, it would
therefore also seem unavoidable to open up again the gate of ijtihad
(of effort) which has been closed in the tenth century. This closing has
consisted in freezing Islamic legal theory at that time by declaring that
a point had been reached at which all essential questions of law had been
thoroughly discussed, rendering thus any further deliberation unnecessary,
if not disruptive and thus condemning Islamic law to immobilism and conservatism
(LE ROY 1995a : 17, WEISS 1978 : 282, HALLAQ 1984 : 287).
4. The Indian Archetype
In
the following pages we will call Indian archetype the archetype
shared by traditional Hindu, Jain and Buddhist conceptions of reality. This
archetype can best be apprehended through the concept of dharma. But
before having a closer look at dharma, let us shortly present the
cosmology in which it is embedded.
In
the Hindu cosmology there is a creation of the world. But it is not a creation
by an exterior God out of the void, but a projection, srishti, of
the non-manifested (Brahman) into the manifested. Srishti is
the passage from the one to the multiple. It is most currently explained
through the differentiation of two fundamental principles,
prâna, energy in its primordial essence, and
âkâsha, substance in its primordial essence. It is the
interplay of these two principles which allow the existence of all things
and beings.The end of the world is a dissolution, pralaya, constituted
by the return of the manifested to the non-manifested. Nevertheless, this
cycle is not unique but repeats itself endlessly according to a regular cyclic
rhythm which cannot be apprehended by the human mind (HERBERT 1988 : 76-79,
VIVEKANANDA 1970 : 373 ff). Although all existence is based on the dynamic
interplay of prâna and âkâsha, which reminds
us of the Chinese structuration of the world by yin and yang,
the Indian is not a dualist world view. Its cosmology rests on a ternary
structure of reality which is seen as made up by three worlds
(triloka).
Further even though there
is God and creation, both are not uniform. There are numerous universes and
God himself manifests himself through multiple forms. As God as such is to
remote to be apprehended by the human mind, he can be rendered intelligible
to us by its personalization. This personalized God is called Ishvara
by the Hindus and can be approached under the aspect of any of its possible
functions, powers or manifestations. He can thus be represented in multiple
ways and called by multiple names. The Hindu monotheism thus accepts, and
even considers as necessary, a parallel polytheism - whose pantheon can seem
very puzzling at the first encounter with its multiple gods and their avatars.
Furthermore above polytheism and monotheism, Hinduism keeps a place for monism
(Advaïta), a doctrine considering that there is only one reality,
that God is not separated from his creation but is his creation. The Indian
world is thus fundamentally plural. If it is hierarchically organized, this
hierarchy is not a linear and rigid one, but a flexible and complex one (HERBERT
1979 : 60 ff and 95 ff, 1988 : 286 ff, VIVEKANANDA 1972 : 99 ff). We thus
find in the Hindu world view, which is also at the basis of Buddhism and
Jainism, a blending of abrahamic, Confucian and animist views. There is a
God creator and a created world organised through a hierarchical principle.
Nevertheless the universe is infinite in number and in time, going through
endless cycles animated by the interplay of two opposite and complementary
forces. At the same time, the Indian world view pictures an eminently plural
world and does not reduce it to a dual structure. It is thus a very interesting
mestizaje as it can give us hints as to the way of conceiving a platform
for mutual encounter which could permit the articulation of our different
cultural archetypes.
Dharma is a central concept in this world view.
It is The structuring principle of life and the cosmos :
Dharma is that which maintains, gives
cohesion and thus strength to any given thing, to reality, and ultimately
to the three worlds
(triloka).
(PANIKKAR 1984a : 39)
On a cosmic level,
dharma is the way in
which one maintains everything, the way in which the cosmos or the balance
in the cosmos, is maintained. At the micro level, dharma is the way in which
every constituent element of the cosmos contributes its share to maintaining
the overall balance. Each element has its own dharma, its svadharma.
As long as each element of the cosmos performs its specific svadharma,
the overall balance does not suffer. As soon as an element , however, deviates
from its own dharma, that is, commits adharma, the balance is
disturbed. (ROCHER 1978 : 5)
It
should also be emphasized that dharma is an eminently plurivocal term
:
The religious man will see in dharma
God's law; the moral man will see it as the interior principle which
provides the criterion for good and evil; the lawyer will see it as law (...),
the psychologist will emphasize tradition, custom, social spirit; the philosopher
will see in it the conscience of the species or the conscience of unity,
which by its will push man to manifest goodness or the sense of unity; the
idealist will see in it the ideal; the realist, the law which underpins the
apparent manifestations of life; the practical mystic will see in it the
force (...) which brings harmony in unity. But actually, dharma is
the principle which is at the basis of all these manifestations, contained
in all of them, and underlying all these conceptions. (MEES quoted
in : Herbert, 1988: 117-118) -21-
Thus dharma not only
inscribes the human beings in society but in the whole universe for which
they become partly responsible and thus, as PANIKKAR (1984a : 39) notes:
(...) a world in which the notion of
Dharma is central and
nearly all-pervasive is not concerned with finding the 'right' of one individual
against another or of the individual vis-à-vis society, but rather
with assaying the dharmic (right, true, consistent ...) or
adharmic character of a thing or an action within the entire
theanthropocosmic complex of reality.
In
this conception the individual cannot be conceived as an abstract independent
entity, as he is only the knot in and of the net of relationships
which form the fabric of the Real. (PANIKKAR 1984a : 40). We will
come back and elaborate this insight in our last part on a dianthropological
praxis of Human Rights. For the moment let us content ourselves with noting
that in this view personality has, like in animist thought, rather a functional
than a substantive character. It is the different statuses of men which will
determine their mutual rights and duties. Furthermore as already noticed,
dharma brings in the idea of a cosmic relation and responsibility
extending beyond the purely human realm. Humankind has the 'right'
to survive only insofar as it performs the duty of maintaining the world
(lokasamgraha). (PANIKKAR 1984a : 41). Last but not least,
by insisting on the universal interdependence of things and beings and by
stressing the need for their harmonious cooperation, the Indian world view
also invites us to take a global perspective on Human Rights and not to merely
see them as the mere assembly of a set of separate and independent rights.
III. Modelling our Common
Humanities as a Platform for Intercultural Dialogue
Before starting our modelling
exercise we should maybe reiterate a warning. Our paradigm of Common Humanities
intents to shed light on the plural character of Humanity. It intents to
emphasize the mutual interdependence of unity and diversity in the constitution
of the Human. It intents to make us aware of the fact that we express our
Humanity, our Common Humanity, through multiple means, in multiple ways,
in our Common Humanities. And all of us do. It is not only different individuals
or different cultures which express themselves differently. Even the same
individual or culture manifests itself plurally. Nevertheless, all individuals
or cultures have some features which especially characterize them. That is
what makes up their original personality. But next to the dominant trait(s),
the individual or the culture also shares the other characteristics of the
Human. One could say that they are a bundle of characteristics : they display
some of them in major - the others in minor, like in a musical composition.
Thus, looking at the others and looking at their differences permits us to
discover in ourselves traits we may have overseen.
Crystallizing our Common
Humanities is therefore just as much learning about the different choices
we have made concerning the traits we play in major, as learning about the
whole bundle of traits we all possess as Humans. In the following developments
it should thus be kept in mind that I do not intent to give a rigid,
essentialising view of cultures and their law. All societies very probably
contain all elements presented below and only differentiate themselves in
the way they coordinate them and play them in major or minor. The rigid
presentation in the forms of models is only necessary to provide us with
tools to think our Common Humanities and thus to be able to engage in authentic
intercultural dialogue. Thus, when I speak of crystallizing this should not
evoke the idea of freezing a reality but rather of rendering conscious the
essence of a reality that was unconscious before.
In
the precedent pages we have crystallized our Common Humanities by unveiling
the different archetypes underlying them. This operation has permitted to
render conscious what usually remains unconscious. It has helped to unveil
the implicit assumptions members of different cultures may have when dialoguing
about Human Rights. This may contribute to shed some light on non Western
critiques of Human Rights and may help to see them as constructive critiques
rather than as attacks by barbarians of a civilized
ideal. It may help to break out of a logic of opposition which seemed to
dominate at the World Conference on Human Rights in Vienna in 1993. It may
also permit to break out of monological dialogue in favour of
dialogical dialogue sustained by diatopical hermeneutics. It may thus permit
to orient future meetings towards a more cooperative dialogue, acknowledging
that unity must not be reduced to uniformity but can exist in diversity.
Keeping in mind our new insights, it becomes easier to understand the originality
of non-Western declarations of Human Rights : like the African Charta of
Human Rights of 1981 which insists parallel to the individual rights on
collective rights, on duties correlative to the rights, and on the right
to development, or like the different Islamic declarations of Human Rights
(the Universal Declaration of Human Rights in Islam of 1981, the Declaration
of Koweit of 1980, the Declaration of Taif of 1981, the Declaration of Ryad
of 1988) which are essentially marked by their stressing of the divine character
of Human Rights, or finally the Asian declarations (Declaration of the
Fundamental Duties of the Asian Peoples and States of 1983, the Declaration
of Bangkok of 1993, the Manifest of Human Rights in China of 1979) which
insist on the necessity of taking into account regional or national
specificities, the importance of collective rights and the right to development
(for the above and for more detail : ROULAND 1995b : 202-204, 1994 : 21-28).
The aim of this part is to
draw on the lessons provided by the precedent pages in order to propose a
synthetic model which can constitute a frame for thinking about Human Rights
in an intercultural perspective. In other words we will try to propose a
platform for intercultural dialogue in which our Common Humanities
could meet in mutual exchange. In order to do so I will present three models
which Etienne LE ROY has given during his lectures on Anthropologie
économique et sociale for the Diplôme d'Etudes
Approfondies Études africaines Option anthropologie juridique et
politique of the University of Paris I - Panthéon-Sorbonne,
1995-1996, and during his lectures on Legal anthropology in the
Master programme of Legal Theory at the European Academy of Legal Theory
in Brussels, 1996-1997. I will then propose a synthesizing model of the precedent
ones inspired by another of LE ROY's models given in these lectures.
The first of these models
is related to the subject of Human Rights. The second is related to the different
normative orders which can be seen as constituting Law. The third is related
to the different kinds of social rules grounding Law. The last
one is a summary, adding the different societal archetypes and locating in
it our different Common Humanities in relation to each other.
1. The Subject of Human
Rights
In
the archetypes we have developed, there appeared three kinds of relationships
between the individuals and their society. In the Western world view it is
the individual as an autonomous legal person (personne juridique)
who is valorized, the state being an assembly of equal individuals. In the
animist it is the human being who is valorized with an equilibrium between
his individual human and his social or collective human
aspect and who forms a community with those with whom he shares his life.
In the Confucian world view, the global society, the collectivity takes
precedence over the individual who is mainly a subject (Figure 1)
:
2. The Different Social Orders
For LE ROY every society seems to know at least four types of ordering in
social organisation which he calls social orders (ordres sociaux)
: the imposed order (ordre imposé), the accepted order (ordre
accepté), the negotiated order (ordre négocié)
and the contested order (ordre contesté). The imposed order
is usually imposed by an exterior and superior instance, in our western societies
mostly by the state. Its regulation is mediated through general and impersonal
rules, best illustrated by state law. The accepted order is the expression
of a socialisation realised in harmony with the values and the representations
of the project of the society. It is in our societies the frame of our daily
casual experience. It is the product of the systems of lasting dispositions
(systèmes de dispositions durables) which BOURDIEU calls
habitus and which ensure that we for example usually stop in
front of a red light, or accept the authority of our teachers or professors
etc ... The negotiated order privileges the resolution of the conflict within
the group where it originated and corresponds to a functional approach to
conflict resolution. It orients itself rather than on rigid norms, on
models of conduct and behaviour (modèles de conduite
et de comportement) and is characteristic of customary law as we have
met it in relation with the animist societies. The contested order rather
than a really autonomous order of regulation is rather a challenge
to the existing order and invites to a rethinking of the dominant order if
one wants to avoid open and violent confrontation (LE ROY 1995c : 34-36,
1997b : 81-84, ROULAND 1988 : 446-448). We can represent the model of these
different social orders as follows (Figure 2):
3. The Legal Tripod
According to LE ROY (1995a : 26) recent anthropological studies show that
Law (droit) rests on three feet : it rests on general and impersonal
rules best illustrated by law (loi - state law) , on models of conduct
and behaviour crystallized as custom, and on habitus, systems of lasting
dispositions in which the relationship to law is incultured and in which
Law is in its daily living represented and interpreted in particular laws,
which rely largely on education. It appears that the normative phenomenon
can only be grasped adequately through the prism of these three
feet or foundations (LE ROY 1995a : 26, KUYU 1995
: 83-84). In our modelling of this prism we will represent the
three feet with their counterparts of social regulation (Figure 3):
It may be interesting to see how the legal tripod may permit to model Law
of different societies in intercultural research by using a table presented
by LE ROY in a recent article (1997c : 131). This table shows the
different valorisations of the three feet or foundations of Law in the order
of importance attributed to them in the Western, Animist, Confucian and Muslim
traditions. It gives also a good visual illustration of our Common Humanities
with its bundle of common traits valorised differently in different cultures
but present in all of them (Figure 4):
4. A Platform for Intercultural Dialogue on Human Rights
Not to get confused, we will first give a model summarizing the models above,
by complementing them with their legal archetypes. Indeed as we have seen
in relation with the different legal archetypes and their logics, different
cultures' Laws always form coherent systems. Thus we can relate the different
archetypes to the different logics which valorise different conceptions of
the individual, different social orders, different foundations
of Law. We should recall here that all societies reveal all these elements
but differentiate each other through the different weight they give to them.
After having given the abstract model we will place it in the context of
the different cultures. The model will thus show the respective relation
of the different cultures with regard to each other, and can thus constitute
a platform for intercultural dialogue. It can constitute this platform, this
topos of encounter, as it helps to determine the respective topoi
of the partners to the dialogue (Figure 5) :
We will now place it in the context of the different cultures. In order to
keep the diagram clear I will only indicate at each summit of the triangle
the corresponding archetype without representing all the other correlated
notions (Figure 6) :
The purpose of this model is not to provide a comprehensive explanation,
but it merely intends to show how a platform for intercultural dialogue could
be conceived and modelled. It is mainly intended to provide us with a visual
support for our pluralistic Human Rights' thought, and to constitute an
intellectual support or platform for an intercultural Human Rights' approach.
It should not evoke a relativistic view of cultures. As already mentioned
above, the elements by which we have characterized the legal archetypes can
be found in all cultures, though they may be weighted differently. Furthermore
the model should not suggest a frozen and immobile picture of legal cultures.
Through time cultures change. The actual picture of a society at one specific
moment would also show us the pluralism of societal organisations in different
fields of socio-legal regulation. Thus, to stay on the purely legal level,
trade law (droit des affaires) in continental Europe for instance
seems much closer to custom and negotiated order than to codified state law
and imposed order. The model should rather try to evoke a platform, a forum
where we can meet and share, and which acknowledges the peculiar enrichments
that our Common Humanities can offer in an authentic intercultural
dialogue.
In his lectures, Etienne LE ROY has also characterized the different Western
streams, stemming either from the Reform (protestants) or from the Counter
Reform (Catholics), those issued of the Counter Reform being closer to the
unitarian archetype of submission than those issued from the Reform. He has
also characterized the conceptions of ancient Rome and of Byzance as well
as the Jewish tradition. As we have not dealt with them in our thesis I did
not include them on the above model, which without doubt can still be improved
considerably. Nevertheless, it already opens up, in its present form, a way
to think our Human Rights problematic in a healthy pluralism,
acknowledging our Common Humanities, our unity in our diversity. This model
invites us also to go further and to reflect upon the Community which our
cultures in their mutual tension and cooperation represented above can give
rise to, and which will have to deal with one aspect left aside for the moment,
though announced through the diagram : the dynamic aspect of our living together,
our actual living together.
The Mulla, who had just been freshly nominated as a judge, heard his first case.
The plaintiff exposed his problem in such a convincing manner that the Mulla exclaimed :
I think you are right !
The clerk of the court asked him to refrain himself, as the defendant had not yet been heard.
Nasrudin was so moved by the defendant's eloquence, that he exclaimed, as soon as the latter had stopped to speak :
I think you are right !
The clerk of the court could not stand it anymore :
Your Honour, they cannot both be right.
- I think you are right ! said Nasrudin.
(SHAH 1989: 67) -22-
In
Part I, we had a brief encounter with our Common Humanities. We have discovered
that different cultures share different outlooks on reality and on life,
declining thus in various ways our Common Humanity into Common Humanities.
We have also tried to show that these different outlooks are not necessarily
contradictory but can be seen as complementary, thus making a mutual enrichment
possible. We have also tried to propose a model which could help us to think
about Human Rights in intercultural, dialogical and plural terms. What we
have not done until now, is to deal with the issue raised above, in the little
story of the Mulla Nasrudin's first trial.
It
may be very nice to agree with everybody by trying to understand him from
within, by looking at things from his topos. But this does not seem
to allow to reach solution, a settlement, and thus does not seem to fit the
demands of legal life.The main problem we will try to deal with in this Part
will therefore be to try to think the pluralism which has emerged in the
precedent Part in the legal field. The whole reflection will be centered
on two main problems : how to think the and and how to think
our practice or rather praxis of Human Rights.
Thinking the and
will invite us to favour cooperation, articulation instead of exclusion or
imposition. Thinking the praxis will invite us to think about Law as legal
phenomenon (phénomène juridique) as ALLIOT defines
it, thus taking into account its social practices, instead of merely thinking
about law, reduced only to its state law aspect and to its rules.
It will be the concept of Community, of Human Community or rather of Human
Rights' Community which will permit us to link those two approaches.
The concept of game in legal
theory will then provide us with tools to analyse and to shape our Human
Rights' Community.
So
let us start by having a look at the possible emergence of
Community as a paradigm for intercultural Human Rights' thought
(Chapter III) before reflecting upon its possible operationalization through
the help of the concept of game (Chapter IV).
Chapter III : Community - A Paradigm for Intercultural Human Rights'
Thought
A paradigm, in the large sense in which we will use it here, is, according
to KUHN, a set of beliefs, recognized values, techniques and methods shared
by a scientific community. It is thus the more or less explicit frame underlying
a scientific community's work (KUHN 1994 : 29 ff, OST 1993b: 364, OST, van
de KERCHOVE 1993a : 192-196). In this Chapter I will try to present the paradigm
of Community in order to permit us to think and to realize the
healthy pluralism needed for a genuinely intercultural conception
of Human Rights. In my opinion thinking in terms of healthy
pluralism in the domain of Human Rights' Law is only possible if we
cease to think in terms of a Human Rights' system and if we start
to think in the terms of a Human Rights Community. This paradigmatic
shift entails, as already noted above, a shift from the emphasis on law
(state-law-like law) on an emphasis on Law as legal phenomenon,
phénomène juridique.
This will lead us to an acknowledgement of the specific social character
of Law and of the existence of legal pluralism or even multijuridisme,
which, according to my use of law/Law, I could translate as
multilegalism. It will further entail a change of perspective
by taking the point of view of the Legal actors rather than that of the
legal system, thus spotting attention on social Legal practices
and so emphasizing the emancipatory aspect of Law, usually too much neglected
in favour of its regulatory aspect.
To be able to grasp the relevance of the proposed paradigm, it is necessary
to locate it in the paradigm from which it emerged and to which, and also
to a large extent against which, it is a reaction. We will thus start by
putting into perspective our approach by expliciting the contemporary dominant
modern paradigm of Law, in which the majority of Human Rights'
thought is still embedded, and which is maybe already changing into a
postmodern paradigm (I). We will then try to propose the concept
of Community as a paradigm for intercultural Human Rights' thought
in order to reflect upon a Human Rights Community (II).
I. The Modern Paradigm of Law and its Transformations
We have quickly learned that the dreams
of the modern epoch were nothing but illusions. Time has unveiled the
imperfections of modern law; it has shown to what extent universalism
was a delusion, and that the supreme reign of law does not solve everything.
The observation of daily legal experience has led numerous legal experts
who are interested in the problems of the foundations of law, to admit that
all law is relative, that there is a pluralism of the sources of law, and
that a return to pragmatism is required. (ARNAUD 1990: 81) -23-
Let us briefly outline what
the modern paradigm of Law consists in (1), before presenting its
postmodern evolutions which, I will argue, should lead us to
a change of perspective, especially in the domain of intercultural Human
Rights' thought, from an emphasis on the legal system to an emphasis on the
legal actors and their interaction (2).
1. The Modern Paradigm
of Law
What is the modern paradigm
? A first answer can be that it is the paradigm which has marked western
thought in the modern age. Historians and philosophers understand this age
as the period expanding from the end of the middle ages until the French
revolution.The lawyers of the European continent extend this period until
the promulgation of the French civil code in 1804 (ARNAUD 1990 : 81). The
modern conception of law can thus be seen as the child of Enlightenment which
was mainly characterized by the central role it assigned to Reason. According
to TOURAINE (1992 : 51) :
Modernist thought affirms that human beings pertain to a world governed by natural laws that reason discovers and to which it is itself submitted. And it identifies the people, the nation, all the individuals with a social body, which also functions along natural laws and which must free itself irrational forms of organisation and domination which fraudulently try to get legitimized by reference to a revelation or to a supra-humane decision.
-24-
Even though dating back to
Enlightenment, the modern conception of law still seems to be quite influential
nowadays, although it starts to be more and more challenged (ARNAUD 1991
: 102). In what does it consist ? In the modern perspective, law
(droit), as rational law, is characterized by its foundation in the
belief that it is universal and that it is through the general and impersonal
law (loi) that the common good can be achieved. State law is thus
equated to Law in general and all other legal phenomena are negated. State
law becomes The Law - there is no more space for the previously accepted
legal pluralism as it represents a potential threat to the State's authority
(ARNAUD 1990 : 81). For COTTERRELL (1992 : 306) :
Modern law is the law of the
Rechtsstaat. Freeing
itself from traditional roots in culture, and discarding old common law ideas
of legal doctrine as an expression of communal values or timeless wisdom,
law became recognised as a technical instrument of rational government for
modern states.
Furthermore, according to
COTTERRELL (1992 : 306) modern law is characterized by its moral and intellectual
autonomy, its comprehensiveness, its unified and systematic structure and
its principled character reflecting the values of modern civilisation. ARNAUD
(1990 : 81) also mentions the legalist positivism which is linked to it and
which is the means of its uniformising systematisation of life in society.
De SOUSA SANTOS highlights another important aspect, already present in what
we have presented above but not yet explicitly formulated : modern law is
fundamentally entrenched in positivism, which he defines as follows :
Positivism is the philosophical
consciousness of knowledge-as-regulation. It is a philosophy of order over
chaos both in nature and society. Order is regularity, logically or empirically
established through systematic knowledge. Systematic knowledge and systematic
regulation are the two sides of order. Systematic knowledge is the knowledge
of observed regularities. Systematic regulation is the effective control
over the production and reproduction of observed regularities. Together,
they constitute the positivistic effective order, an order based on certainty,
predictability and control. Positivistic order is thus Janus-faced : it is
both an observed regularity and a regularized way of producing regularity.
(...) Modern science and modern law are the two sides of
knowledge-as-regulation.(...) Scientism and statism are the main features
of modern rational law as it developed in the West during the nineteenth
century. (de SOUSA
SANTOS 1995 : 73)
De
SOUSA SANTOS' contribution is relevant as it shows the links between Law
as a social practice and as a scientific theory. It makes us aware of the
fact that ways of thinking, paradigms, more or less delimit the scope of
how a thing can be thought of. In a positivistic paradigm, as defined by
de SOUSA SANTOS, it thus seems for example difficult to think of Law in terms
of emancipation or in the plural terms we have encountered while dealing
with Law in animist societies.
The last but not the least
feature of the modern paradigm relevant to us is its individualism. To us
the notion of individual, of person, on which our
Human Rights' declarations are based, may seem self-evident . But as MAUSS
(1995 : 362) remarks, this notion is only the outcome of our specific historical
evolution :
from simple masquerade to mask, from character
to person, to a name, to an individual, from there to a metaphysical value,
from a moral conscience to a sacred being, from there to a fundamental category
of thought and of action (...) Who knows if this 'category' that all of us
here believe to be founded, will always be recognized as such ? It is only
formed for us, by us. -25-
Let us briefly outline what
modern individualism consists in. For that purpose, I would like to emphasize
two of its traits : the uniform and abstract conception of the individual
and its central place in the thought of social organisation and Law. These
two traits are interrelated. As ARNAUD (1991 : 107 ff) remarks, the focus
of interest on the individual is closely linked to the emergence in natural
law thought, with Occam, of voluntarianism, legal positivism and subjectivism
which will lead to the modern paradigm with the individual in its center
(ARNAUD 1991 : 120 ff). As DUMONT (1991 : 87 and 97) writes :
Law which in its most fundamental aspect was an expression of the order discovered in nature by the human mind, becomes in its totality expression of the 'power' or of the 'will' of the legislator. Furthermore, while law was thought of as a just relation between social beings, it becomes social recognition of the power (potestas) of the individual. Occam is thus the founder of the 'subjective theory' of law, which in fact is the modern theory of law. (...)
For the moderns (...) Natural Law (...) does
not deal with social beings but with individuals, this is to say men who
are self sufficient as made in the image of God and entrusted with reason.
Therefore (...), the fundamental principles of the constitution of the State
(and of society) have to be extracted or deducted, from the inherent properties
of man, considered as an autonomous being, free of any social or political
binding. To deduce from this logical or hypothetical state of nature the
principles of social life can appear as a paradoxical and ungrateful task.
It is nevertheless into what theoreticians of modern Natural Law ventured,
and it is by doing so that they prepared the bases of the modern democratic
state. -26-
For our purpose, I would describe
the modern view of the individual as a system's view
of the individual. He is an abstraction permitting the operationalization
of a rational system of law, which is composed of the State, its law, and
its addressee, the individual. As the whole system is intended to emancipate
Man by permitting him to live a good life through rational means, the notion
of individual rights becomes paramount. The individualism embodied in modern
law sees individuals above all as entities abstracted from social and cultural
contingencies, characterized and completely autonomous as to the way in which
they want to lead their lives (COTTERRELL 1992 : 119). They thus need rights
in order to act, and also to be protected against the State they have instituted.
It is interesting to observe that, through rationalization and the linked
systematisation process, the individual, though formally remaining at the
center of the system and still viewed as a homo faber, in fact gets
dissolved in an abstraction.
Of
course, modern law and the modern vision of law cannot be reduced to the
simple picture portrayed above. De SOUSA SANTOS in his Toward a New Common
Sense (1995 : 56 ff) gives a good perception of the complexity of the
trajectory of modernity, or should we maybe even speak more appropriately
of the trajectories of modernity, or even of
modernities. If we have drawn a simple, unified picture, we should
not forget that, from the outset this legal modernity contained its
own contradictions (COTTERRELL 1992 : 307) which are maybe crystallizing
nowadays more visibly than before. We should also keep in mind that there
is no clear limit between modernity and what some call
postmodernity and that it may not even be very appropriate to
talk of a qualitatively different postmodern condition of Western
law (COTTERRELL 1992 : 309). We have in this section only tried
to present, in a modelled form, our current paradigm, in which in my opinion
the large majority of Human Rights' thought is still embedded, and which
does not seem to provide an adequate frame for a fruitful research on the
intercultural Human Rights' problematic. Furthermore, this paradigm is more
broadly questioned as a paradigm of thinking of Law, even in a solely Western,
monocultural context. As COTTERRELL (1996a : 294-295) notes,
in the context of a reflection upon Legal Theory and the Image of
Legality :
Images of system, cohesion in law, together
with the idea of law's intellectual distinctiveness as doctrine and practice,
seem less plausible than even in the quite recent past. (...) legal theory
will address lawyers' (and citizens') concerns by continuing to examine the
nature and conditions of
ratio in law (...)
But it must recognize the very nature of ratio as dependent on context and
therefore variable, disputed, and contingent. (...)The recognition that law's
community is not a matter of unproblematic unity but of complex diversity
puts the nature and consequences of this diversity at the heart of legal
theory's concerns. (...) In legal studies a sociological perspective is a
necessary corrective to legal romanticism. It alerts us to the fact that
the search for the morally meaningful legality will be unproductive without
rigorous empirical study of the complex and varied conditions in which legality
is to be sought.
ARNAUD, in his article
Repenser un droit pour l'époque postmoderne (1990 : 81-82)
invites us to rethink a postmodern Law, on tracks parallel to
those outlined in the quotation above. He advocates the acknowledgement of
the relativity of all law which has to be sustained by its legitimacy in
the eyes of those to whom it applies or who practice and use it, the
acknowledgement of the pluralism of the sources of Law which cannot be reduced
to state law, and finally the withdrawal from legal idealism in favour of
pragmatism. Let us follow ARNAUD's reasoning and try to outline, on this
basis, the requirements for intercultural Human Rights' thought. I will take
ARNAUD's proposition as an invitation for a change of perspective which could
be seen as the shift from a legal system's perspective to a
legal actors' perspective and which will permit us to reflect
upon the emancipatory aspect of law and upon the concept of
individual.
2. A Change of Perspective : From a Legal System's
to a Legal Actors'
View ?
We
will try to outline the stakes in an intercultural Human Rights' approach,
to leave the classical modern conceptions of Law in order to
take into account legal relativism, legal pluralism and legal pragmatism.
We will present our argument by taking the standpoint of the legal actors,
rather than the one of the Human Rights' system, although we
do it in order to reflect upon a Human Rights' system which could
stand up to the demands flowing from such a change of perspective. As we
have mentioned in our introduction, large populations of the world do not
live under a regime of Human Rights as we perceive them - they
are outside the System. Our universal system seems
to apply more readily to Western societies than really universally. That
is the reason why I think that, instead of starting to tackle our issue from
the standpoint of a universal solution which we have shown in
our first part to be rather a local universalized solution, we should try
to approach it from our concrete problematics which have a universal scope.
It is this actor's perspective, this pragmatic approach, which
will demand us to acknowledge legal relativism and pluralism. As VANDERLINDEN
(1989 : 153) writes :
Let us now consider the problem from
the standpoint of the individual. He and he alone finds himself in a situation
of legal pluralism. It is his behaviour which is governed by multiple and
various regulatory orders, be they of a legal or non-legal nature, which
issue from the various social networks to which he belongs and which pretend
to impose upon him their own regulatory and, possibly, 'legal' orders. It
is he who will have to make a choice between these mechanisms in determining
his behaviour. It is at this level, that which so many political theorists
somewhat complacently call the basis, that a possible conflict in socio-legal
regulation will acquire its full meaning. Thus, instead of looking at the
legal pyramid from the top, from the centres of decision, from the standpoint
of power, one is brought to contemplate it at the level of ordinary men in
their daily activities.
Legal pluralism is necessarily paralleled by legal relativism, as this quotation shows. It emphasises relativity of state-law, as the existence of other regulatory orders is also acknowledged. State-law thus does not appear as an all powerful, absolute tool for social engineering, abstracted from all socio-cultural conditions in which it is supposed to apply. We rather seem invited, instead of thinking in terms of one all-pervasive regulatory field monopolistically organized by the state, to think in the terms of semi-autonomous social fields as developed by Sally Falk MOORE. This is important as it seems to permit to break out of a social engineering view on Human Rights in order to elaborate a Human Rights' Community, as we will see below. MOORE reminds us (1973 : 730) that :
Since we live in a period in which the
potential effectiveness of central planning and the use of law as the tool
of social engineering are heavily emphasized, it is perhaps worth stressing
what is probably obvious, that by no means all, nor even the most important
social changes necessary get their principal impetus from legislated or other
legal innovations, even in centrally planned systems. (...) Legislation consists
of conscious attempts at social direction. But clearly societies are in the
grip of processes of change quite outside this kind of control.
Therefore she (1973 : 720,
742) proposes an approach in terms of semi-autonomous social fields,
which she describes as follows :
The approach proposed here is that the small field of observation to an anthropologist be chosen and studied in terms of its semi-autonomy - the fact that it can generate rules and customs and symbols internally, but that it is also vulnerable to rules and decisions and other forces emanating from the larger world by which it is surrounded. The semi-autonomous social field has rule-making capacities, and the means to induce or coerce compliance; but it is simultaneously set in a larger social matrix which can, and does, affect and invade it, sometimes at its own instance. (...)
The concept of the semi-autonomous social
field is a way of defining a research problem. It draws attention to the
connection between the internal workings of an observable social field and
its points of articulation with a larger setting.
MOORE's concept of
semi-autonomous social fields may open up ways permitting to
take into account non-legal impetuses which can contribute to
the elaboration of a fruitful ground for the growing of Human Rights and
to theorize the articulation of different relevant semi-autonomous Human
Rights' fields. It may permit to study, in relation to the legal tripod presented
in Part I, the articulation between different orders of Human Rights'
law, understood in a very broad sense, including local practices aiming
to realize similar ideas as our Human Rights even if not explicitly stated
in those terms. This may permit us to prepare a fertile ground for global/local
social change towards a Human Rights' ideal. We seem also invited
to think legal pluralism in plural terms, as LE ROY (1996a : 7) advocates.
He argues that until now legal pluralism has rather be thought of in a unitary
way based on the principle of the encompassing of the contrary. The legal
order is constructed as the referent, the encompassing category. Other legal
experiences, which are not state-law, are explicitly or implicitly constructed
as inferior (LE ROY 1996a : 3-4). He thinks that the anthropological
detour may permit to conceive legal pluralism, or
multilegalism (multijuridisme) in a plural way as
we have for example encountered it in the animist societies. In this view,
legal pluralism is the expression of multiple specialised and interdependent
regulations which valorise complementarity of the differences (LE ROY 1996a
: 5). But before all, as he says (1996a: 8) :
(...) multilegalism (multijuridisme)
which integrates the idea of the multiple in the Legal idea must be approached
not as a set of static injunctions or of sanctions but as an open, dynamic
system, like a game or a process of which the rules must be reformulated
through a new paradigm. -27-
This emphasis runs parallel
to MOORE's emphasis on law as process. She argues (1983 : 6) :
The continuous making and reiterating
of social and symbolic order is seen as an active process, not as something
which, once achieved, is fixed. The view is taken that existing orders are
endlessly vulnerable to being unmade, remade, and transformed, and that even
maintaining and reproducing themselves, staying as they are, should be seen
as a process. To try to understand something about law and society in these
terms is to address the question how such processes and counterprocesses
operate together, and what the preconditions are for reproduction or
transformation. It is far more than a set of enforceable rules and the logical
principles which may be inferred to lie behind them.
We
will try to acknowledge law's plural and processual character in the Human
Rights field by presenting the paradigm of a Human Rights' Community. But
before doing so we still need to highlight the demands of practice because,
as MOORE (1983 : 4) notes :
Social transactions usually take place
in the service of objectives to which legal rules are merely ancillary shapers,
enablers or impediments. Conformity to the rules is seldom in itself the
central objective.
And she argues (MOORE 1973
: 743) that :
The law (in the sense of state enforceable
law) is only one of a number of factors that affect the decisions people
make, the actions they take and the relationships they have. (...) The operative
rules of the game include some laws and some other quite effective
norms and practices.
This stresses a point very
relevant to intercultural Human Rights' thought and especially for countries
to which the content as well as the form of the Human Rights' rules are foreign
and where the possibilities of their enforcement (the necessary institutional
structures) are widely lacking. The decentering in our approach by paying
attention to actual legal regulation (régulation juridique)
on local levels (which can be more or less narrow) and its interference with
legal regulation on more global levels (which can be more or less broad)
seems thus especially paramount in reflecting upon Human Rights' Law in
non-Western societies, in which state-law is often only a very far away reality
for big parts of the population.
The failures of the export
and the reception of the Western model of the state, stemming from the Western
colonizations, should make us sceptical towards any kind of evolutionary
optimism. Africa's example since the independances is striking (ROULAND 1988
: 360-387). Immediately after the access to independence, Western law was
perceived as The key to progress and to the access of modernity.
Traditional laws were seen as obstacles to development which had to be eliminated
as quickly as possible (CONAC 1980 : XVI). Today, thirty years later, this
view has shown to be largely an illusion. The mimetism has turned out to
be to a broad extent ineffective or even counterproductive. As CONAC (1990
: 17) remarks, the rule of Law cannot be decreed, it must be lived,
wanted and culturally assimilated. The process of export and reception
has also given birth to some unforeseen mestizajes, to use again de
SOUSA SANTOS' term. And nowadays one seems to assist to the birth of a new
African law which again integrates and builds on traditional African conceptions
of Law (ALLIOT 1980).
LE
ROY (1991 : 118, 1997c : 134) speaks in the contemporary context of a
taming of the Leviathan which gives rise to a new emerging law,
which is neither the traditional law, neither the imported state-law, and
which he calls law of practice (droit de la pratique).
This emerging law has to be located in the context of the emergence of new
common cultures which build as much on modernity as on local traditions and
thus give rise to a neo-customary law, a mestizaje between indigenous
and exogenous legal cultures. This law of practice is characterized by its
realist, pragmatic and future oriented outlook (LE ROY 1997c : 135). It can
take a pragmatic or a more learned (savant) aspect, depending
on whether it uses the written form, knowledge about official institutions
and the capacity to manipulate the actors and the administrations (LE ROY
1997c : 136-137). This emerging phenomenon gives nowadays rise to a real
legal and judiciary pluralism in African states, which according to LE ROY
(1997c : 137), must now be institutionally organised so as to permit the
transition to an African rule of law.
This kind of transition towards
an African rule of law appears thus as something very different from the
legal or institutional transition, advocated by the World Bank
(LE ROY 1997c : 135), and which we traditionally have in mind when thinking
of the democratization processes, but which seems to be highly tainted by
ethnocentric evolutionism. It is a transition which does not go in the direction
of the spreading of a uniform universal model of the rule of law, but on
the contrary seems to prepare the emergence of original systems. Furthermore
these systems themselves seem to be rather rooted in a plural
approach to Law rather than in the uniform approach we cherish. It may be
interesting to contemplate a lengthy quotation of LE ROY (1990b : 118-120)
on law in practice in a Senegaleze context, in order to approach
a phenomenon which to us is uncommon and may be quite puzzling :
By favouring negotiation and by orienting the subject of law (justiciable) towards the search for consensus which is less concerned with applying the law but than with reconciling points of views and interests, these societies are inventing a new type of law which does not need to be expressed in the canonic form of a legal code, nor to be enunciated by a legislative instance.
This experience which we design as law of practice, in the double sense that it depends on its effective usages and on those who adhere to it, does only very incidentally rely on precedents. Rather than by working in reconstituted time like in a criminal trial, or in real time (for juvenile justice, (...), the African mediator invests in the future and in the long term of the social relations to come.
Further, he is embedded in a very interesting new societal context : the one of new common cultures. (...) Though opposing themselves to official cultures, à la française in the cases observed in Western Africa, these new cultural manifestations do not show an orientation to the past and a privileging of ethnic foundations, except (...) within some fundamentalist Muslims from Kaolak to Kano. (...)
It is a real culture that is emerging. It can be called common not solely because of its popular character but also because it shares common traits with the previous cultures. Rooted in the local values like the native cultures from which it spread, sensitive to a tolerant and world open Islam, aspiring to immediate efficacy, and concerned about performances, at least political ones, like in modern societies, this wolophone culture is both synthesis, and thus mestizaje of previous cultures and the manifestation of a postmodernity. As a culture of action, of make do (...), of the tensional management of contradictions, wolofisation expresses modalities of a life in society without caring to sacrifice to the cult of modernity. It is not the institutions which are invoked but their beneficiaries. (...)
As the reflection developed, one could perceive that it is not through law or subject of law (justice et justiciable) that a certain pacification of the social relations is sought. Less and less sensitive to our fictions and to our legal myths, African societies say bluntly that State justice is only one arena of negotiation among others, often less efficient than direct management of the conflict. For them, law is the putting into forms of conflicts, emergence of consensuses and management in the long term of solutions which allow the reproduction of the principal articulations of social life.
All these explanations are both familiar and commonplace to the African and the Africanist and astonishing to the foreign observer (...)The institutional representations which have founded modernity from the XVIth to the XVIIIth century are now outdated. Without knowing it we are already in post-modernity (...)
We have not found a legal subject
(justiciable)but have in turn discovered the emergence of a new aspiration
to social justice and to the reconciliation of Africa with its history.
-28-
I
think that this last quotation has provided us with a good illustration of
the challenge that is facing us of developing a mestizaje of Human
Rights which will only be possible through the acknowledgement of Legal
pragmatism, relativism and pluralism. It has also reminded us of law's aspect
of emancipation. De SOUSA SANTOS (1995 : 25) links it to
knowledge-as-emancipation which for him is knowledge entailing
a trajectory between a state of ignorance he calls colonialism and
a state of knowing which he calls solidarity, and which he opposes
to knowledge-as-regulation which for him entails a trajectory
from chaos to order. We will develop this idea further below
by presenting the paradigm of the Human Rights' Community.
But before we should emphasis
that our shift of perspective has also affected our view of the
individuals. It has rendered them very real, and has given a
rather plural outlook on them. They are not defined anymore in an abstract
and uniform way, but through their action in different legal worlds
to use BOLTANSKI's and THEVENOT's expression. They term worlds
the different situations characterized by a specific grammar of
justification through which we go in our daily life (1991: 177). These
worlds are thus ideal worlds rather than social worlds. They
distinguish the inspired, the domestic, the civic, the merchant and the
industrial world and the world of opinion (1991 : 192 ff). In their view
the individual becomes a concrete plural and becoming being who can be
characterized through his passing from one to the other of these ideal worlds
in his evolution in the social world(s) permitting him to play the social
game (1991: 266-267) :
(...) in a differentiated society, each
person is every day exposed to situations pertaining to distinct worlds and
must be able to recognize them and to adjust to them. These societies can
be qualified as complex in the sense that their members must
possess the necessary competence to identify the nature of the situation
and to go through situations pertaining to different worlds (...) Although
the game is tightly limited by the setting of the situation, a model of multiple
worlds gives the actor the opportunity to avoid a challenge
(épreuve) and to contest its validity or even to turn around
the situation by engaging in another challenge valid in another world. It
thus includes the possibility of critique of which determinist constructions
cannot give account. -29-
II. The Human Rights'
Community - A New Paradigm for Human Rights' Thought
Let us start by clarifying
the scope of the proposed paradigmatic change (1) before presenting the paradigm
of the Human Rights' Community (2)
1. The Scope of the
Paradigmatic Change
We
will take as a starting point a quotation already referred to further up
in our general introduction :
The truth is that, after centuries of modernity, the absence of a future cannot be filled out by either the past or the present. The lack of future is but an empty future.
We must, therefore, reinvent the future by
opening up a new horizon of possibilities mapped out by new radical alternatives.
Merely to criticize the dominant paradigm, though crucial, is not enough.
We must also define the emergent paradigm, this being the really important
and difficult task.
(de SOUSA SANTOS 1995
: 479)
In
this part we will follow de SOUSA SANTOS' invitation. We will try to propose
Community as a new paradigm for Human Rights' thought. This presentation
of Community can be seen as what de SOUSA SANTOS (1995 : 481) terms
heterotopia. Let us recall that if utopia is the
imagination of new modes of human being which can constitute an alternative
to the present ones but are projected in an elsewhere or a nowhere, for de
SOUSA SANTOS, heterotopia, Rather than the invention
of a place elsewhere or nowhere is a radical displacement
within the same place : ours. It is a shift from orthotopia
to heterotopia, from the center to the margin. Although not strictly
applying his reasonings, and thus using his term in a maybe slightly different
sense than he does, I think that this idea of a radical displacement inside
our global system in order to propose an alternative global system,
captures very well what I will intend to do in the following pages by presenting
the paradigm of a Human Right's Community. In this thesis we have already
made a number of decentering steps which we will now try to articulate together
in the form of the Community paradigm.
Our first steps away from
the centre were made in Part I. From monological imposition of a transcendent
Human Rights' ideal we have shifted towards proposing a dialogical dialogue
on this ideal. We have thus not only operated a shift from abstract Reason,
to reason which is linked to its socio-cultural surroundings, but also from
a monocentric to a polycentric perspective on the Human Rights' problematic.
We have decentered our outlook on Man and on Law, without nevertheless loosing
sight of both. To recall the metaphor of the windows : we have started to
look at our problematic from different windows, offering different perspectives,
instead of contenting ourselves with the view out of our own window. This
shift of perspective was already crystallized in the concept of Common Humanities
which intended to make us aware of the twofold nature of Humankind. Like
a prism, this concept invited us to think both our common abstract humanity,
the white light, and the different shapes or colours into which it has been
diffracted in the concrete and diverse human experiences, like the white
light is diffracted into the colours of the rainbow. By putting Common and
Humanities at the same level Common Humanities invited us to think both human
unity and diversity, both human transcendence and immanence at the same time
- and not one prior and superior to the other. If the notion of what we share
in common, our humanity, is essential in Human Rights' thought,
the correlated notion of what differentiates us, of how this
humanity is concretely lived through different ways of being
human, in our humanities, is too. This aspect of living and living
together is what leads us from our concept of Common Humanities to our concept
of Human Community
In
this Part II we have therefore continued our decentering, this time in relation
to our modern conceptions of Law. We have shifted the point of view from
the system to the actor. We have thus operated a
paradigmatic shift from universality to relativity, from uniformity to plurality,
from theory to practice. And we now try to propose the paradigm of Community
which should enable us to think differently about Human Rights in order to
enable a different practice of Human Rights. As de SOUSA SANTOS (1995 : 489)
remarks :
The paradigmatic transition is double
: epistemological and societal. The two transitions are autonomous but intimately
related. Alternative forms of knowledge generate alternative social practices,
and vice versa.
Before dealing more exclusively
with the Community paradigm, we should underline that the paradigm of Human
Community or of Human Rights' Community can only be understood in its relation
to the paradigm of Common Humanities, and also to the one of Dianthropological
Praxis of Human Rights. As I have outlined in my introduction, the three
concepts Common Humanities, Human Community and
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights are in my mind three
paradigms constituting the three cornerstones of a broader paradigm, a pluralist
myth, which could underlie intercultural Human Rights' thought. Although
all are dialectically related to each other, the paradigm of Community plays
a special role because, apart of its own original contribution, it is this
paradigm that can link together, that can constitute a space of encounter,
of concrete crystallization and of mutual enrichment for the two others.
It
is in their interrelation that it becomes clear why I have chosen to speak
of Common Humanities and Human Community and not of Common
Humanity and Human Communities, which would maybe appear more natural.
We usually tend to think of our Humanity as an abstract category encompassing
all human communities which are seen as its concrete manifestations. By doing
so we stress a transcendent unity. But as we make a sharp distinction between
mind and matter, between the ideal and the real, we nevertheless sometimes
tend to think of Others, of people belonging to other communities
as radically different from ourselves. It is the view of an abstract shared
Humanity and the recognition of ethnic, cultural, religious etc ... belonging
to different communities, which gives rise in my opinion to radical cultural
relativist views.
The problem seems to be that
in the modern paradigm, as de SOUSA SANTOS puts it, we are mostly applying
knowing-as-regulation. This means that we think of chaos as ignorance and
of order as knowledge (de SOUSA SANTOS 1995 : 25). The rational paradigm
is marked by its uniformity. Reason discovers universal and uniform laws
which underlie the seemingly chaotic universe. It thus permits to order this
chaos by reducing the plurality to uniformity. Rational abstract concepts
are thus tainted by this universality and uniformity. But we have seen,
especially while dealing with animist thoughts, that to reduce plurality
to uniformity is only one way to conceive order. Not only this
: we have seen that for the animist societies uniformisation was seen as
a threat to their harmony, to their order. Our challenge, in
order to be able to engage in intercultural human Rights' thought, as we
have already shown it, is to learn to think in pluralist terms. I thus found
it necessary to introduce the plurality where it is generally implicitly
always lacking : at the very root of our rational thought on Human Rights
- there where we are accustomed to find unity before it gets
contaminated by the contingencies of life and thus degenerates
in plurality and diversity. We have to learn to think pluralism plurally,
which is only possible if even our fundamental axioms are plural. This
necessitates to change our outlook on chaos, order, unity and diversity.
We have to fundamentally reorient our way of knowing, as de SOUSA SANTOS
(1995 : 25-26) reminds us :
The paradigm of modernity comprises two main forms of knowledge : knowledge-as-emancipation and knowledge-as-regulation. (...) In the terms of the paradigm, the mutual binding between the pillar of regulation and the pillar of emancipation implies that these two forms of knowledge balance each other in a dynamic way. What this means is that the knowing power of order feeds the knowing power of solidarity, and vice-versa. The fulfilment of this dynamic equilibrium was entrusted to three forms of rationality mentioned above : the moral-practical rationality, the aesthetic-expressive rationality and the cognitive-instrumental rationality. In the last two hundred years, I have been arguing, the cognitive-instrumental rationality of science and technology overcame the other two forms of rationality. In this process knowledge-as-regulation won primacy over knowledge as emancipation : order became the hegemonic way of knowing and chaos became the hegemonic form of ignorance. (...)
This is the predicament we are in now, and
must get out of. And there is no other way but to reassess
knowledge-as-emancipation (...) This implies, on the one hand, that solidarity
be turned into the hegemonic form of knowing, and, on the other, that a certain
degree of chaos be taken in as a consequence of the relative negligence of
knowledge-as-regulation. This entails two significant epistemological
commitments. The first one consists in the reassessment of chaos as a form
of knowledge rather than ignorance. This transition can be observed within
modern science itself in the theories of chaos. Rather than transcending
chaos, order coexists with it in a more or less tense relation. (...) Chaos
invites us to a praxis that insists on immediate effects, and warns against
distant effects, a style of action that privileges a transparent, localized
connection between action and its consequences. That is chaos invites us
to a prudent knowledge. Prudence has some family resemblances with pragmatism.
(...) The near is to be privileged as the most decisive form of the
real.
To
think in terms including chaos and acknowledging differences, we seem invited
to make a step towards animist conceptions of order
which consists in the complementarity of differences, in the solidarity in
our differences instead of a uniform order. As LE ROY (1997a : 15) writes
:
It is in the perspective of an intercultural model that it will be necessary to renew the principle of the complementarity of differences from a philosophical, political and practical point of view.
Already acknowledged in the animist and Indian traditions, not really foreign to the Confucian and Muslim traditions, this principle of the complementarity of differences gives rise in the western tradition to difficulties which research must subsequently identify and contribute to resolve. (...)
In the present state of affairs of anthropological
research, and taking into account anthropology's inscription in a Western
concept of science, and thus in its world view, priority must be given to
the enrichment of western conceptions underlying Human Rights,
by valuing again the idea (noumen ?) of respect of the other and by
reintroducing the principle of the complementarity of differences. Without
denying the difficulties which appear in front of us, we must be convinced
that to face the turbulences which we can foresee, only an ethical and
epistemical exigencies can possibly found a common future and a pacified
society. -30-
The challenge of contemporary
intercultural Human Rights' thought thus seems to be to search for its roots
in an eminently pluralist myth, of which the paradigm of Common Humanities
is one manifestation - on the more intellectual plane. But as de SOUSA SANTOS
says, and as we have already observed above, a plural outlook on reality,
stressing the solidarity and complementarity of differences, also obliges
us to shift from theory to praxis, from system to actors. That is why we
have to conceptualize the paradigm of Human Community. The Human Community
permits us to think of our Common Humanities not in an abstract, uniform
and immobile way but in a concrete, plural and processual way, in the way
FINNIS (1996 : 135) invites us to do :
(...) it is helpful to begin by thinking
of community or association not as a community or an association (an 'entity'
or 'substance' or 'thing' which 'exists', acts, etc.) but rather as community
or association, an ongoing state of affairs, a sharing of life or of action
or of interests, an associating or coming together. Community in this sense
is a matter of relationship and interaction.
It
is the paradigm of a Human Rights' Community as the ground, where knowledge
and regulation-as-emancipation can flourish and where an intercultural
mestizaje of Human Rights can emerge, which I want to present now.
My paradigm of Community is thus closer to the legal archetypes as we have
presented them in our first part, than a sociological reality - the sociological
reality of my Community coinciding with what we usually term Humankind. The
proposal of this paradigm is thus really a radical displacement within
the same place. We are still talking of the same reality : Humankind.
But by looking at it from a completely different perspective in fact we radically
change what we see.
2. The Human Rights' Community
We
will start by presenting the paradigm of a Human Rights' Community (a) before
showing its relationship to actual communities (b).
(a) As already indicated, the paradigm of the Human
Rights' Community is heavily rooted in the lessons to be drawn from the
communitarian archetype of differentiation characterizing animist societies
and presented in Part I. Let us briefly recall the main features of this
archetype by showing their respective relevance for intercultural Human Rights'
thought.
First of all it is rooted
in plurality and is characterized by a perspective viewing life as the tensional
though harmonious dynamic interplay of different forces. This aspect seems
most important in intercultural Human Rights' thought as it invites us to
acknowledge plurality without immediately reducing it to chaos (as ignorance),
and to not to think in terms of exclusion but of inclusion. It may thus permit
us to start thinking pluralism in pluralist terms, as LE ROY (1996a : 7)
advocates : by acknowledging unity only where it imposes itself as the sum
of identifiable elements and not as a set of which parts are negated or reduced.
The Community paradigm may thus permit us to proceed along the principle
of addition instead of the principle of subtraction. Plurality and relativity
of Law are in that perspective not seen as the enemies of Law but as potential
cornerstones for an efficient Law which needs to be articulated around a
common ideal.
Second the communitarian archetype
favours the resolution of conflicts inside the group where they arose, in
the womb of the family or of the village. It is linked to a logic
of responsibilization. It leaves the responsibility of its future within
the society or community. It stays thus centered in itself and does not abandon
its responsibility for its life to an exterior and superior instance. This
has two consequences : negotiation (palabre) is valued and praxis
is valued. The valuing of negotiation seems extremely relevant in our domain.
There is no global superior instance to which we could refer to and who could
tell us what to do. There is no superior instance to which we could abandon
the responsibility of our common human future. This is all the more so as
for the moment a universally accepted and effective Human Rights'
system is not established and appears rather to be a demand, a requirement,
which still needs to be realized. To establish such a system
we thus need to negotiate. We need to find a solution in the womb
of our Common Humanity (Humanities). Trying to impose an abstract perfect
humanity will not do. We will have to build our Common Humanity
in our Human Community by building on the best of our Common Humanities.
Therefore negotiation demands dialogue, which as we have shown cannot be
reduced to chatting or a mere exchange of points of views, but has to be
understood as a real journey through different cultural logics, which may
permit the emergence of a new intercultural myth of Human Rights.
But the challenge takes us
further than that. As we have seen, the acknowledgement of chaos in our concepts
of order invites us to privilege praxis over systematising theory, the local
perspectives in their mutual enrichment over a global unified perspective.
That is why, in my mind, an intercultural Human Rights' system will never
possibly be a System but has to be thought of as a Community
marked by ongoing dialogue in which a common praxis is built by the
interfecundation of praxises. The Community, contrary to the System, is not
closed to real life and to the acknowledgement of multiple perspectives.
On the contrary, the multiple perspectives linked to the various praxises
are at the core of Community. Dialogue is as much linked to negotiation as
it is linked to praxis. Dialogue is a constant rediscovery of the other and
a constant reinvention of our common future. It is not to be reduced to a
means of finding knowledge which could then be institutionalised. It can
contribute to a certain kind of institutionalisation, but not of a closed
system but rather of an open dynamic system which, because of
its multiplicity, its dynamism and its link to praxis, I prefer to conceptualize
as Community. Dialogue is in that perspective deeply embedded in the paradigm
of Community. Community is the additive structuring principle which can sustain
the never ending process of invention, reinvention, production and reproduction
of our human society, or rather community.
We
have now briefly outlined what we consider to be the main pillars of a Human
Rights' Community as a paradigm for intercultural Human Rights' thought in
a healthy pluralism : plurality approached through dialogue and the principle
of the complementarity of differences, and praxis which is closely linked
to the responsabilization of the Human Rights' actors. To present this paradigm
I have, in a short text Droits de l'Homme - Vers une communauté
comme écosystème ? declined Community as
écosystème (ecosystem),
écho-système (echo-system) and
et/co-système (and/co-system) (EBERHARD
1997) : Community seems to me a viable ecosystem for plural Human Rights
thought as it emphasises a praxis as echo-system, meaning a system
based on dialogue in which we advance by the echoes we receive from our theory
and practice when they encounter theories and practices originating from
different points of views, and a praxis as and/co-system, meaning
a system that emphasises the principle of addition and of complementarity
of differences.
(b) We have outlined our paradigm. We should now
say a few words as to its relations to real communities. We will
first reflect upon the extrapolation we have operated of the communitarian
archetype from the structuring principle of animist societies to the structuring
principle of our global society. We will then reflect upon its operationalisation
through different Human Rights' communities.
The communitarian archetype
functions in communities which ALLIOT (1980a : 156 ff) characterizes by a
triple sharing : sharing of the same life, sharing of all its specificities
and sharing of a common decisional field. The first sharing is the sharing
of a same space, of a same daily life, of games, food, ancestors, language
etc... (ALLIOT 1980a : 156) The second is the sharing of all the specificities.
Communities are composed of different specific groups accomplishing specific
functions. The specificity of the groups (ex : peasants, blacksmiths ...)
and their complementarity is thus at the core of the group's cohesion and
survival. This second sharing is thus the sharing in the complementarity
of the group's differences (ALLIOT 1980a : 157). The third is a sharing of
common rules of the game, the community being defined by the
area where its rules, which it has in its own control, apply (ALLIOT 1980a
: 159).
In
the context of these given communities which have been studied
by anthropologists these three sharings are given. For our Human Rights'
Community I think that they can be said at the same time to exist and still
need to be constructed. I will try to show that all the elements are there
to invite us to such a triple sharing but that we still need to enable this
sharing by taking a Communitarian outlook on these elements.
We need to think in terms of Community in order to enable the realisation
of a Community. As we have said above, our paradigmatic shift is epistemological
as much as social and consists in heterotopia, in the radical displacement
of ourselves in the contemporary system. I will try to show that
the displacement in favour of Community does not seem to run counter to what
is sociologically happening or to what can happen, even though it is not
self-evident and demands conscious effort.
It
may at first be puzzling to speak on the global level of a shared
life. Does not our whole thesis tend to show that we live our Common
Humanity in our Common Humanities, in original and specific ways, which stems
from the fact that we live different lives? We should of course not neglect
this aspect. But at the same time our whole thesis only makes sense in a
paradigm in which we acknowledge more and more our global condition,
our world culture, or the common challenges to humankind
may they be ecological, economical or political ... We thus certainly share
more and more of a common life - even if that does not mean that we become
homogeneous. It only means that besides our local horizons we also share
in a broader global horizon. And our life is influenced by both. If globalisation
is for the moment rather a phenomenon which imposes itself and
which does not yet really seem to have been assimilated by us,
I think that by looking at our global condition through the eyes of Community,
we may be able to assimilate it. Our pragmatically shared global condition
may thus little by little turn into a shared global living-together sustained
by intercultural founding myths and shared references. This common
life or rather life in common which seems to become more
and more important as we increasingly have to assume responsibility for our
own global future, seems only possible to emerge if we acknowledge a sharing
in the totality of our differences. A life in common can only emerge if we
do not deny any culture the access to the sharing. And sharing is giving
and taking. It is mutual enrichment. It is the acceptance of complementarity
in the differences.
This thesis tries explicitly
to contribute to the sharing in the totality of our differences.
Remains the sharing of a common decisional field.We should note that
theoretically this common decisional field already exists as we talk of the
universality of Human Rights and as there exists a working international
law. Nevertheless, I feel that this common decisional field has to be rethought
in order for it to become really common and that decision is
not monopolised by some (few) members of the Human Community.
In
order to start building a common life, a federative myth, like the one of
Human Community is necessary. In order to share the totality of our specificities
and a common decisional field it becomes necessary to rely on Human Rights'
communities which in their interrelation can make up the Human Rights'
Community.
COTTERRELL (1996c : 5-6)
distinguishes four ideal types of community : traditional community
(living in the same geographical space or sharing the same language),
instrumental community or community of interest, community of belief and
affective community. Our Human Rights' communities would in this terminology
be communities of interest. They can be defined by their location in different
regions and on different scales (the village, the infrastate region, the
state, the suprastate region, the continent, the world for example) or by
their specific function (rebuilding of peace, protection of children, action
against torture ...). It should be clear that belonging to one of these
communities does not exclude belonging to others at the same time. As we
have advocated, by basing ourselves on BOLTANSKI's and THEVENOT's idea of
plurality of worlds, the individual in our Communitarian view must be conceived
as eminently plural : to talk in terms of Community only makes sense if we
acknowledge the plural character of the individual and his plural inscription
in different communities. Otherwise our Communitarianism could
quickly turn into some kind of communalism. This communalism, although
acknowledging the plurality of communities nevertheless stays committed to
a unitary way of thinking, as it recognizes a plurality of communities but
conceives them as monopolistical entitities. If it admits a choice of the
community of belonging it sees this choice as exclusive - multiple allegiances
are not permitted.
In
order to be effective Human Rights' communities must of course be rooted
in local communities (local at the different levels as illustrated
above), of which the state is only one, and often not the most relevant one.
It is only the reliance on local communities which can permit active involvement
of the concerned people and can assure the proximity between regulation and
the specific moral outlooks, views of life and socio-economic conditions
of the concerned populations. It becomes thus necessary to reflect, as COTTERRELL
does in his Law's Community (1996a), upon the relationships between
Law and Community in order to understand the possible contributions communities
can make to Law and to step out of a purely static view of Law which does
not seem to be able to stand up to the challenges presented by the intercultural
Human Rights' problematic. As COTTERRELL (1996a : 296) writes :
Although contemporary law's dominant
character is as a policy-instrument of centralized government, social studies
of law should not necessarily adopt the policy-maker's agenda, nor, indeed,
the policy-maker's view of law's scope and nature. An appropriate focus is
on the diversity of regulatory forms and requirements arising directly out
of experience in particular social fields. Socio-legal studies might include
within the scope of 'the legal', alongside state law created by the agencies
of centralized government, many other forms of institutionalized doctrine
constituting socially significant regulation. In this way social science
might point towards new understandings of law's relation with community.
At
this point, we will not take this enquiry any further as it would lead us
to far away from our present problematic. Let us instead, just give a last
quotation of COTTERRELL (1996a : 322) which shows the important link of a
reflection on Community as a plural archetype for intercultural Human Rights'
thought, and the reflection on Community as way to give Law back to
the citizens and to make it morally meaningful :
Thus, even judicial rhetoric from relatively unified legal systems of contemporary states suggests that a concern for relationships between law and community is a concern with legal and moral pluralism. The issues that emerge as central are how to express in regulatory form the values of numerous communities and how to develop regulation to co-ordinate, integrate, and respect the experiences of social existence characteristic of different communities.
An emphasis on community values is thus, in
contemporary conditions, an emphasis on the localized as against the centralized,
and on diversity as against uniformity. The reason is that any emphasis on
a shared underpinning of values as a defining element of community becomes
unrealistic unless accompanied by a corresponding recognition that the scope
for agreement on values, or even for significantly shared social experience,
is necessarily limited in contemporary conditions of social complexity. To
postulate, with some sociological sensitivity, the utility of a concept of
community is necessarily to recognize diversity in social arrangements and
radical pluralism in moral life as the essential conditions of existence
of those areas of moral agreement that can underpin social solidarity
today.
We
have presented our paradigm of a Human Rights' Community. Let us now try
to see how this paradigm could be operationalized in Legal science and
practice.
Chapter IV : Operationalizing the Human Rights' Community Through the
Concept of Game
In this Chapter we will try to see how the idea of a Human Rights' Community
could be operationalized in Legal theory through the concept of game. Of
course, game and Community are two different paradigms
of legal thought. Nevertheless, they share some common perspectives. That
is why putting them in relation may turn out to be conducive in providing
useful insights in the domain of game as much as in the one of
Community. I will start by presenting van de KERCHOVE's and OST's
paradigm of game in legal theory (I) before presenting a processual approach
to Law which can more specifically help us to think of the Human Rights'
Community. This approach has been developed by the Laboratoire d'anthropologie
juridique de Paris and is illustrated in the form of the Jeu de l'oie,
which corresponds to the British Snakes and Ladders game and
which one might also term Legal Monopoly (II).
I. The Concept of Game in Legal Theory
We will present here van de KERCHOVE's and OST's ludic approach to Law. This
approach is still a systemic, although not a closed one. As we
have advocated, we seem invited, in an intercultural reflection upon Human
Rights, to leave the systemic paradigm in favour of a Communitarian
paradigm. Nevertheless, the development of a Human Rights' Community cannot
avoid tackling problems of legal systematicity. The construction of a Human
Rights' Community will partly have to integrate classical approaches to Law.
A certain degree of systematisation on different levels will be necessary.
The Community will have to be put into forms, even though these forms may
not be the forms of a unique system, but of partially articulated
systems. Institutionalisation, at least to a certain extent, is necessary
for a working Human Rights' Community. It is thus important to
explore ways in which a Community outlook on Law could be reconciled
with a system outlook.
The paradigm of game may offer a welcome bridge. Maybe that this bridge is
especially needed in a Western context, marked by systematic thought and
practice of Law. It may also be that this bridge may be less relevant in
other cultural contexts. But for us the paradigm of game may permit to open
up our actual legal experience towards a more communitarian approach
to Law. The interest of the game approach to Law lies in the fact that it
tries to bring the actors into the picture of the legal system, and favours
a dialectical, complex approach to Law, and to the relations of Law and society.
The dialectical approach can be mainly characterized by the fact that it
tries to think the and, the fertile in-between between
opposites. It thus favours a plural approach to Law which recognizes the
plural aspects of the legal system as well as of its actors. As OST (1997b
: 3, 10) writes :
(...) we think that we can see more deeply in the very idea of game an explanatory model or paradigm for the understanding of law in general. On this respect, the idea of game offers to legal theory a conceptual frame that can, by analogy, enlighten many aspects of legal phenomena. This frame includes concepts such as play, player -partner and adversary -, stake, rule of the game, move, score, scorer, out of play, fair play, and so on. The idea of game also offers a logical structure in terms of which we can conceive legal theory, that is a dialectical and paradoxical structure (an and-and way of thinking) that we can substitute to a binary and disjunctive structure (an either-or way of thinking) that is more traditional.
(...) a legal system is animated by a game
that, because it involves the intervention of players who are not exclusively
its own product but also participate in other social games, necessarily modifies
itself in response to its environment. Therefore, it seems impossible to
adopt any theory of a legal system that would insist radically on its closeness
or openness, and a dialectical conception of the relations between legal
system and social order is obviously required.
The dialectical game approach
to law may thus permit us to bridge the gap between Law's Community
(ies) and the Legal System, as the dialectical approach
shares in the plural logic of the communitarian archetype - even though it
stays in my opinion on a lesser level of acknowledging of pluralism and practice
than the communitarian archetype. Indeed, as it still is a systemic
view, it postulates a unity of the system. The different polarities in which
it is inscribed, which constitute the frame for the legal play (which is
movement in a frame), are still dialectical polarities. This means that they
are polarities inside a same system of reference. Van de KERCHOVE and OST
develop their paradigm of game more especially in the frame of five pairs
of polarized notions : strategy and representation, cooperation and conflict,
reality and fiction, regulation and uncertainty, internality and externality
(OST 1997b : 2, and more generally: van de KERCHOVE, OST 1992). The novelty
of the dialectical approach is to acknowledge those polarities and to see
them as complementary, rather than as opposites. It thus permits to think
in a plural and complex way :
It appears that in pair with the model
of game goes a dialectical method. This dialectical theory aims at providing
a coherent representation both of the legal phenomenon itself and of the
epistemology of its science and the ethics of its practice. On every of these
planes plurality is substituted to unity, recursivity to linearity, graduality
is preferred to binarity, while uncertainty (which does nevertheless not
mean complete random), adapted to present times, is assumed and replaces
the pseudo-security which the thoughts of simplicity believe to grant.
(OST, van de KERCHOVE 1993a: 191) -32-
However, this approach does not attain the dialogical character of the Communitarian paradigm, which reveals itself paramount in intercultural Human Rights thought. As we have seen while presenting the dialogical dialogue, intercultural pluralism cannot be reduced to dialectical pluralism, which presupposes a shared unitary myth and a shared frame of rationality. Different cultures share in different myths in which rationality grows differently. These different myths are not in a dialectical relation. I have argued that they can nevertheless be in a dialogical relation if we acknowledge the idea of a Human Community in our Common Humanities, which opens our mutual understanding to our respective praxises and their correlative witnesses. Rationality is thus in the Communitarian paradigm not only invited to think together poles which seem opposed inside a rational system underlaid by a common myth. It is also invited to acknowledge different practices and experiences and to think them together. This experiences are not necessarily opposed. And one should even avoid to think of them in terms of opposition as this may lead us into the trap of the encompassing of the opposite, thus hindering us to discover what is really different behind what appears as different to us. PANIKKAR (1984c : 205, 212-213)writes in relation to the dialectical and dialogical approaches to reality :
(...) the ultimate nature of reality does not have to be dialectical. If we postulate it to be so, we do it by the already dialectical axiom that affirms reality to be solely or ultimately dialectical. Reality has no other foundation than itself, and if we assume it to be dialectical we are already postulating what reality has to be, and imprisoning it in the dialectical frame, large and flexible as one may conceive this latter to be. The postulate of the dialectical nature of reality is an extrapolation of the conviction about the dialectical nature of the mind ; it subordinates reality to mind.
(...) It is one thing to assert that thinking
tells us what being is and another thing to make being utterly dependent
on thinking. In other words, the justification of dialectics does not depend
on the often uncritically accepted hypothesis that the nature of reality
is dialectical. Reality certainly has a dialectical aspect, but this aspect
does not have to be all of the real. It is in this hiatus between thinking
and being that the dialogical dialogue finds its
ultimate
justification.
It
seems to me that every approach in terms of systems necessarily tends to
reduce plurality to unity and that the only way to think pluralism plurally
is to break out of a system's approach in favour of a Communitarian approach.
Let us not forget that the attempt to render pluralism and complexity through
plural and complex unifying models (systems) is still an attempt towards
unification. Thus the game model and its dialectical method may appear quite
revolutionary. This is because it commits an epistemological break from a
Cartesian logic of excluding opposites to a logic acknowledging their
complementarity :
To isolate objects (...) from their environment
and from the observer who studies them (...), to establish linear and
hierarchical relationships between these elements : that is peculiar to
rationality, to the Cartesian paradigm. Philosophy of the
excluded third (tertium non datur), solidly anchored in
the principles of identity (A=A) and of non-contradiction (A is not non-A).
The dialectical model of complexity is, on the contrary, the model of the
included third. This model presupposes that recursive relations
of interaction between the distinct and nevertheless solidary elements are
established, as for example between the object and its environment, between
the observed and the observer, between cause and effect, between internal
and external, etc ... (OST, van de KERCHOVE 1993a : 201) -33-
The innovation consists in
moving away from a partial hierarchical representation of reality excluding
the contraries, to a comprehensive way of representing it reconciling them
and showing their dialectical interdependence. This evokes the circular symbol
of the Tao showing the intertwined yin and yang which
we have already encountered and which van de KERCHOVE and OST (1992 : 108)
use as one illustration of their dialectic approach, although they see their
approach more as an ever open spiral than as a closed circle. What strikes
us in their approach is its circularity which takes precedence over hierarchy
emphasised in former approaches. But if circularity can evoke complementarity
and comprehensiveness, it is nevertheless not the only way to think of
complementarity, and is not to be equated to comprehensiveness. It may be
that it is particularly attractive to us as it seems to be based on an
egalitarian outlook on life. Thinking in terms of of a dialectical circularity
is thinking in terms of two theoretically equal poles. But we have seen that
other ways to think of complementarity and comprehensiveness exist. Animist
thought with its eminently plural outlook on the world is one illustration.
Indian thought (especially advaita), with its hierarchical outlook
on the world in which oppositions are resolved and constructed as complementary
by being put on different hierarchical levels, is another one. This should
make us aware of the fact that there is not just one way of thinking plurality,
complementarity and globality. And it is to prevent us to fall into the illusion
that thinking of Law in terms of game in a plural, complementary and dialectical
way necessarily gives us a comprehensive outlook on Law. The paradigm of
game is not an all comprehensive view on the legal phenomenon in that it
does not exclude any point of view but integrates them all - we must not
forget that all points of view are integrated from a specific perspective
: the dialectic one. But why then dwell on the paradigm of game if we advocate
the necessity to leave dialectics in favour of dialogue and system in favour
of community in the intercultural context ? It is, as already said, to enable
to build a bridge between the Community and the system, the global
Human Rights' Community and our local Human Rights' system, our present episteme
and the emerging one.
In
one of their articles, OST and van de KERCHOVE put their paradigm of game
in relation to four paradigms influential in social sciences in their general
orientation as well as in their focus on Law (1993a). These paradigms are
the paradigms of interest, of system, of actor, and of field (champ).
I would term those paradigms as systemic as they are underlaid
by a rationalistic abstracting and systematising methodology. By this I mean
that they emphasise one aspect of reality, one point of view. They then construct
a global picture of reality from this point of view by drawing the rational
consequences of this point of view and by thus constructing explicative systems.
The difference to the Communitarian approach we propose for intercultural
Human Rights' thought is that we always try to approach our problematic globally.
Nonetheless, we never get a global perspective as our outlook on reality
always depends on the view out of multiple windows, and not only out of one,
even if it is a huge one. We meet the demand of globality not by trying to
see globally but by trying to understand the links and the articulations
between our different local perspectives. Looking at our specific problematic
from all points of view which may be relevant, and trying to articulate the
so gained insights does not enable us to propose comprehensive explanatory
systems, but only partial models which can prove their usefulness in their
application to concrete problematics. The following paragraphs try to give
an idea in what sense the paradigm of game can play for us the role of a
bridge between systematic and Communitarian approaches to Law.
The paradigm of interest,
well illustrated by utilitarianism, permits to shed light on the instrumental
and strategic dimension of legal activity. The problem is that to do so it
often neglects to consider the concrete individual or collective actors and
the sociological contexts in which they are embedded. It thus looses some
of its explanatory power as it turns into a rationalisation of the real which
heavily simplifies it by limiting itself to an abstract, axiomatic maximisation
of personal interests or of those of the largest number. The paradigm of
game seems to permit to keep the insights of the interest paradigm but without
falling into excessive reductionism. Indeed the notion of game, through the
stakes of the game, opens an analysis in terms of interests. But at the same
time it emphasises the players who through their activity try to get what
is at stake. And it emphasises the game as such which gives sense to the
players' actions and fixes the rules of the game. Furthermore the idea of
game draws attention to the symbolic aspect of the actions
(Wertrationalität) and does not limit itself to their instrumental
aspect (Zweckrationalität). It even highlights the dialectic
relationship existing between those two poles as game is always struggle
for and representation of (OST, van de KERCHOVE 1993a :
209-211).
The paradigm of system is
maybe the fundamental aspect of modern legal theory. Different sorts of
systematization have been proposed. The systematic approach permits to give
a coherent picture of Law. But it seems to privilege logical approaches to
Law which emphasise its deductive, formal and axiomatic character. Internal
inconsistencies or the dependence of the legal system on its environment
often seem to be neglected. The paradigm of game, although acknowledging
a certain systematicity of Law by giving account of a certain closure of
the legal phenomenon, nevertheless suggests that its borders are partially
changing, porous and reversible. It also suggests that the legal system is
in-between order and disorder. If it insists on the necessary regulation
and ordering of legal activity it nevertheless accepts a part of indecision.
If it accepts the objective dimension of the Legal phenomenon as a globality,
it also recalls the necessary creative subjectivity of its actors. And again
it permits to think all those aspects in a dialectical relationship (OST,
van de KERCHOVE 1993a : 212-214).
The paradigm of the actor
seems to become more and more relevant in social sciences since the last
two decades. The actor is reemerging as the actor of the market, the social
actor understood in a functional sense through its social integration and
the historical subject which is defined by his capacity to make
sense out of his life. The paradigm of game invites to think the actor not
in opposition to the system, but in its complementarity to it. It also emphasises
the plural identity of the actor who can play different games (OST, van de
KERCHOVE 1993a : 214-215)
Finally the idea of field
(champ) is closely related to the idea of game and could maybe be
enriched by the latter (OST, van de KERCHOVE 1993a : 216).
It
seems to me that by acknowledging the different points of view and by integrating
them in a coherent approach by putting them into dialectical relationships,
the paradigm of game, although remaining in a systemic view,
as it privileges the game point of view which orders the rest of reality,
permits an opening up to the Communitarian paradigm we defend to tackle the
intercultural Human Rights' problematic.
Let us now present a specific
game, the Jeu de l'oie, or Legal Monopoly, which in my
opinion can constitute not just a bridge towards our more classical,
systemic conceptions of Law, but serve as a tool enabling us
to put into practice a Communitarian methodology, a Communitarian tool to
think about the Human Rights' Community. It is a plural tool which may permit
us to think a healthy Human Rights' pluralism plurally.
II. The Jeu de
l'oie or Legal Monopoly
Before presenting the approach,
a short word on its name and on its translation. The Jeu de l'oie
is a French game which can be compared to the British Snakes and
Ladders game. Its literal translation is the game of the
goose. It has the form of a spiral. The purpose of the game is to arrive
first at the final square and thus to win the goose. The players advance
their draughts by throwing a dice. In French Jeu de l'oie permits
a pun as it can be understood as jeu de lois, a game of laws. I have
chosen to translate it as legal monopoly as monopoly is an internationally
well known game and as the term Legal Monopoly has a similar
double connotation as implied by the homeophonic character of the French
pun.
The spiralic Jeu de l'oie
is the child of a processual approach to Law which has first used a circular
support for its presentation, on the model of Monopoly, and which has been
developed through the research of the Laboratoire d'anthropologie juridique
de Paris (LAJP). It has been mainly used for research in the domain of African
land law and agricultural reforms and for research in the domain of the justice
of minors. As LE ROY says, the processual approach privileges two essential
poles : the point of view of the observer and the individual and collective
goals (enjeux) that are sought to be achieved (LE ROY 1988a : 36).
It thus joins our actor's perspective and our emphasis on praxis. For our
presentation here we will mainly rely on LE ROY's presentation in
Prolégomènes à une analyse dynamique de la gestion
foncière (1996b). There he presents the Jeu de l'oie
in the context of the search for an African rule of law in the specific context
of land management (gestion foncière). According
to him it is not sufficient to acknowledge the existence of multiple, specialised
and interdependent laws. One must find ways to operationalize this view in
order to permit the crystallization of a concrete device permitting to realize
a working legal system, or as we prefer to say in our context, a working
legal community. For us the Jeu de l'oie is relevant as it provides
a Communitarian approach to our Human Rights' Community which permits to
operationalize it. The jeu de l'oie enables us to focus on the dynamic
character of the Human Community and to represent it. It thus provides us
with a welcome complement to our more static models in relation with our
Common Humanities. It permits us to undertake the necessary epistemological
break which can permit us to think the articulation between traditional Western
state-law and the regulations inspired by living law or by the
law of practice, between a global Human Rights' Law and local
Human Rights' Laws.
The processual analysis
crystallized in the Jeu de l'oie has its roots in dynamic
anthropology as initiated in Great Britain by Max GLUCKMAN and in France
by Georges BALANDIER and as represented in the United States by Sally Falk
MOORE, and can ultimately be traced back to MALINOWSKI's approaches to Law
(LE ROY 1988a : 35, 1996b : 187). As LE ROY notes, it encounters François
OST's and Michel van de KERCHOVE's paradigm of game, as the dynamic approach
permits to escape classical hermeneutics and permits to take into account
the part of improvisation, the necessary margin of uncertainty which is part
of any social game and which Law has to express in the form of rules and
norms. It permits to approach the complexity of Law as a dialectical relationship
between certainty and uncertainty, which can be summed up in the idea of
the open texture of Law. Furthermore LE ROY acknowledges that
the Jeu de l'oie places itself in the in-between paradigm
advocated by OST and van de KERCHOVE (LE ROY 1996b : 188), the five couples
of opposition framing law and presented above being the raw material of the
processual analysis.
Let us now present the approach
of Law through the Jeu de l'oie which constitutes a support for our
dynamic approach to Law. Instead of moving randomly on the squares according
to the values shown by the dice, in the social Jeu de l'oie, the player
is seen as moving according to the social and legal positions from which
he can expect to win (or to loose) advantages in the social game. The Jeu
de l'oie is constituted of ten squares. On the last one we do not find
a goose as a price but the rules of the social game itself which are effectively
shared by the largest number. The way to the last square, to the rules of
the game, is made up by the following squares representing different social
and legal positionings :
1. Statuses, 2. Resources, 3. Conducts,
4. Logics, 5. Scales, 6. Time processes, 7. Forums
for interaction, 8. Social orders, 9. Stakes, 10. Rules
of the game.
Below is a representation
of the Jeu de l'oie (Figure 7) which may help us to visualize
more clearly the dynamic aspect of the game. I have adapted it from the Jeu
de l'oie presented in Espace public et
socialisation dans les métropoles : quelques
préliminaires à une problématique interculturelle
(LE ROY 1995c : 39) to fit our purpose.
Let us now have a closer look at the different squares. In the frame of this
thesis I will content myself with presenting the general methodology of the
Jeu de l'oie. I will not try to explicitly apply it to our Human Rights'
problematic. Nevertheless, the link between this processual approach and
our concept of a Human Rights' Community will appear very clearly. I will
also try to present relevant perspectives on the intercultural Human Rights'
problematic that can be opened through the different squares.
Square One : Statuses
The first square are the statuses. Man is a social being. As such he is always
embedded in a network of relationships. He does not exist independently as
our abstract individualism may suggest. Thus in order to take an actor's,
or player's perspective, we must start by locating him in the social context.
Every individual has a plurality of statuses, which are related to his
inscription in different collectivities or communities. We have already
encountered this plurality of the individual and of its inscriptions in different
communities above by presenting BOLTANSKI's and THEVENOT's idea of plurality
of worlds and by discussing legal pluralism (see especially our quotation
of VANDERLINDEN on p 52). A distinction can be made between his legal statuses
and his social statuses (LA ROY 1996b : 190-193). In our research this square
is relevant as it invites us to draw attention to the relevant communities,
and legal orders for the tackling of different Human Rights' problematics.
It permits to locate from which Human Right's community, as defined above,
an analysis is led. It thus conditions all the further choices of analysis.
Furthermore, the square of statuses invites us, in relation to the model
of the subject of Human Rights presented in Part I, to reflect
upon the possible status of the Human Rights' actor or/and subject : is it
the citizen, the legal person, the human being, or still another status ?
As outlined in Part I, in African societies marked by the Communitarian
archetype, an analysis in terms of status reveals itself as essential.
Square Two : Resources
The square of resources invites us to consider the material, human and ideal
resources available to the actor. Different ways of practising Human Rights
may necessitate different material resources. Our Western way for example
needs a huge bureaucratic and administrative institutionalisation. This may
be a pragmatic obstacle to the transfer of our model in contexts where the
necessary infrastructures are lacking and cannot be established and entertained.
But not only the material resources must fit to enable an effective Human
Rights' practice. The ideal world of the concerned societies must provide
a resource for Human Rights' theory and practice. If cultural specificities
are taken into account in the local praxises of Human Rights, the local ideal
worlds can be turned into such a resource instead of being perceived as an
obstacle, and of being an obstacle to an unadapted and exterior system. This
may also help to resolve the problem of often lacking material resources
- building on local conceptions and already existing legal practices seems
to be more realistic than trying to create a completely new system out of
the blue. In this context the acknowledgement of human resources also becomes
very important. We often neglect them as we favour institutional thought.
But human relationships, networks, communities are what constitutes our living
together. They hold a tremendous potential for the realisation of a Human
Rights' ideal. The square of resources also invites us to reflect upon globally
mobilizing projects or intercultural myths or ideals which could foster the
Human Rights' Community. Let us not neglect the power of ideas. Before being
put into practice things are thought of, conceived, even if this can happen
in a more or less conscious way and if there may be quite a gap between theory
and practice.
Square Three : Conducts
Nowadays conducts find a renewed interest as it shows that models of conduct
and behaviour lie at the core of all legal systems. Conducts can basically
be envisaged either as tactics or as strategies. Tactics are reactive or
adaptative conducts. They are the support of our practice in daily life.
They suppose the ability to take chances, to evaluate situations. They permit
to display the habitus, our encultured systems of lasting dispositions. They
are also the precondition for strategies. Strategies are more long term oriented.
They aim at mobilising resources, selecting the most efficient statuses,
in order to achieve specific goals through social, political, economic action.
It is through tactics and strategies that the actors' models of conduct and
behaviour are operationalized. Sometimes the actors apply these models, sometimes
they try to adapt or modify them. But they always try to use them in a way
permitting them to achieve their goals. They thus introduce us to the logics
existing in a social field and which we will deal with in the next square
(LE ROY 1996b : 195-196).
Focus on tactics and strategies is important because it provides a glance
at the feed-back that Human Rights' policies can produce. They
capture attention on what is actually done with the proposed Human Rights'
system. It can thus open to a rethinking of the proposed model rendering
it more effective. The focus on tactics and strategies also invites us, as
we will develop further in square six on time processes, to reflect upon
the frame of our actions. Do we have to respond to immediate problems (an
acute crisis for example which could degenerate in gross violations
of Human Rights as was the case for example in former Yugoslavia or
Rwanda), or are we trying to build common and solid bases for the future?
In which temporality do we inscribe our action ?
Square Four : Logics
As we have already seen, there is not one legal logic. We can at least
distinguish an institutional and a functional logic. This square invites
us to think of both and to think them in a complementary and not in a mutually
exclusive way . We will not dwell on them here as we have already extensively
treated them above. But this square can also invite us to leave the purely
legal domain. As we have noted in our introduction, thinking of our Human
Rights' Community is closely linked to the thinking and structuring of our
global condition. What are the predominant logics in globalisation thought
and discourse ? Is it an economic logic which conceives globalization in
terms of market ? Is it a cultural logic seeing it in terms of cultural
imperialism, relativism or mestizaje ?.. What is the relationship
between those logics ? What are the relevant relations to think and practice
a Human Rights' Community between politics, economics, law ? Must new logics
be invented and be put into practice ?
Square Five : Scales
This is another very important square. We may get a very blurred picture
of the analysed social game if we do not locate it in a space of observation.
We must choose our scale of analysis which will determine our perspective.
As LE ROY (1996b : 198) reminds us : what is true on one scale is not necessary
true on another, because of a different qualification, and thus of a specific
use. It can be very productive here to deepen de SOUSA SANTOS' approach to
Law as a map of misreading (de SOUSA SANTOS (1987). He writes
(1987 : 282) :
The main structural feature of maps
is that in order to fulfil their function they inevitably distort reality.
(...) Maps distort reality through three specific mechanisms and since they
are used systematically they become intrinsic or structural attributes of
any map. Such mechanisms are
: scale,
projection and symbolisation. (...) Maps should be convenient
to use. There is thus a permanent tension in maps between representation
and orientation. (...) In the analysis of the relations between law and society
we should substitute the complex paradigm of scale/projection/symbolisation
for the simple paradigm of correspondence/non-correspondence.
More directly related to scales,
he writes (1987 : 287-288) :
The legal developments reveal the existence
of three different legal spaces and their correspondent forms of law : local,
national and world legality. (...) Local law is a
large-scale legality.
Nation state law is a medium-scale legality. World law is a
small-scale legality. This concept has broad implications. First,
it means that, since scale creates the phenomenon, the different forms of
law create different legal objects upon eventually the same social objects.
They use different criteria to determine the meaningful details and the relevant
features of the activity to be regulated. They establish different networks
of facts. In sum, they create different legal realities. (...) Thus the different
legal orders operating on different scales translate the same social objects
into different legal objects. (...) We can only compare or contrast social
interests and degrees of class consciousness within the same legal space.
The difficulty lies in that socio-legal life is constituted by different
legal spaces operating simultaneously on different scales from different
standpoints. So much is this so that in phenomenological terms and as a result
of interaction and intersection among legal spaces one cannot properly speak
of law and legality but rather of interlaw and interlegality. More important
than the identification of the different legal orders is the tracing of the
complex and changing relations among them. But if while doing this we forget
the question of scale, we may find ourselves in the same distressing situation
as a tourist who forgot to pack the voltage transformer that would enable
him to use his electric razor in foreign country.
So
in order to stay clean shaved during our intercultural Human
Rights' journey let us not forget about scales, their interrelations and
their articulations ! This square also invites us to shed new light on the
role of Human Rights' communities on the global, supra-state regional, state,
infra-state regional and local levels and on more or less local initiatives,
like for example the different non-Western declarations of Human Rights.
It invites us to see their interrelations and to think about their articulation
in order to permit the emergence of a Human Rights' Community at the global
level.
Square Six : Time
Processes
Processes are to historical
analyses what scales are to geographic analyses. Although, processes and
scales are different paradigms, both are interrelated. Sally Falk MOORE has
underlined that a processual analysis is not merely analysis of social change.
It also has to be considered as the way in which diverse experiences acquire
meaning and coherence in relation to a specifically chosen period (LE ROY
1996b : 201, and see MOORE 1983 : 42 ff). It is related to our square of
conducts dealing with tactics and strategies and also to the one of scales.
De SOUSA SANTOS' analysis on scales presented above can be transposed here
from the spatial to the temporal field. The emphasis on different temporalities
is all the more important as we sometimes tend to think of Law as timeless,
as above time, as eternal. Even if we acknowledge that Law can change through
the ages we seldom are aware of the fact that society is not determined by
a unique temporality, attuned to Law, but that it shares in different
temporalities. It may thus be useful to draw temporal maps of
our societies. The three temporalities retained here are the macro-processes,
the meso-processes, and the micro-processes which remind us of de SOUSA SANTOS'
large-scale legality, medium-scale legality and small-scale
legality in the spatial field.
The macro-processes correspond
to large periods of time, at least several decades but usually more. An example
of a macro-process would be the emergence of the modern conceptions of Law
or the process maybe in the making presently towards postmodern
conceptions of Law. The meso-processes correspond to the period of a generation,
after which the meaning of founding events get lost. Thus for example for
the contemporary African elites, the access to political independence does
not bear the same signification anymore as for the first heads of government,
at least in terms of legitimacy. The meso-processes can be approached through
the important political choices leading to reforms or the play of alliances
between actors or through the observation of the changes of public opinion
expliciting cultural shifts in the approaches to societal problems. The
micro-processes are processes lasting a few months, at the most of a few
years, periods during which the founding event is always remembered. This
remembered founding event provides justification for solidarities, oppositions,
conflicts or struggles which are of the domain of tactics evoked above. It
is in the micro-process that the daily social game is plaid and where the
actor can deploy all his social skills (LE ROY 1996b : 201-202).
In
our intercultural Human Rights' thought this square is important as it puts
into perspective our Human Rights' tactics and strategies in relation to
the scale and process in which they find themselves embedded. This square,
as suggested above, also invites us to rethink the role of time in Law, and
to leave the current tabula rasa approach. Past, present and future
are realms interrelated and very influential on our practice of Law, the
past been linked to our memory, our traditions, the future being linked to
our prospects, and the present being in some sense the point of articulation
of both. And we should not forget the density of our present in which different
temporalities exist which have to be coordinated and which, in fact, reflect
our multiple pasts and possible futures. The analyses developed by OST seem
here very relevant to me (1996, 1997d), although I cannot further develop
these ideas here. Let us just quote a passage of OST's synthesis of his article
Déployer le temps. Les conditions de possibilité du temps
social (1997c : 1 and 3-4) to have a glance of the offered perspectives
:
The aim of this text is to reflect upon the conditions of possibility of the constitution of social time. A negentropic social time (which means creative), a human time filled with meaning.(...)
Between the immobility of the time of eternity and the empty fleetingness of fleeing time, the voice of public opinion and of political action, creative of organized memory (Arendt) arises (...) To be capable of history (Hegel), societies must be able to fertilize (make interact) the memory of the past by the expectations of the future and the project by experience (Ricoeur). (...) In order to do so, we must rethink the notions of generation, of humanity and of heritage (patrimoine). This inscription in duration should nevertheless not be reduced (...) to the repetition of the same. (...) Time, in an open society, is thus partly undetermined : it is the time of praxis, different of the time of the programmed manufacturing of things (poiesis). We must remember this with regard to all antidemocratic political philosophies which would like to replace the (political and collective) acting by the (technocratic and elitist) doing. (...) We will both have to affirm the right of everyone to his own rhythm, and to think the conditions for a harmonisation of temporalities which cannot be reduced to the timing of physical time (planning-timing) and must not lead to a synchronization (mise au pas) of the whole society (...)
Return to square one ; on one side Kronos
: an arbitrary power, violent and solitary, associated to a static temporality,
without past or future, without event or initiative ; on the other side the
Hours : symbols of harmony in the City, associated (...) to a dynamic,
fertile (negentropic), alternating and plural temporality. -34-
Square Seven : Forums of
Interaction
This square is a transitional
square between the previous (statuses, resources, conducts, logics, scales,
time processes) and the following ones (orders, stakes, rules of the game).
We can say that the forums of interaction are constituted through all the
squares we have seen above. They are the places in which actors in their
statuses mobilize their resources, and turn them into conducts according
to logics. All this in order to project themselves in a more or less near
future in reference to their scale of action. The processes observed here
are always processes of confrontation and of negotiation. Of confrontation
because the forums are a meeting place for different and often diverging
interests. Of negotiation because at least minimal consensuses must be found
in order to maintain the social contract. As we will see in the
next square, solutions can be formalised differently according to the privileged
social orders, in more or less adequate ways in relation to the pursued
objectives, which constitute the substance of our square nine, the stakes
(LE ROY 1996b : 202).
Forums, places of encounter and exchange are paramount for the regulation of the social game. But as LE ROY notes, they must be adapted to the problems they intend to tackle. They must also be invested by a certain authority so that its decisions can bear concrete effects. In Africa, for example, the context seems critical as often neither the traditional forums like the chieftains' tribunals (tribunal de chefferie) or the council tree (arbre à palabre), nor the modern forums constituted by administrations, legal institutions or parties enjoy the necessary legitimacy and authority to pacify social relationships, protect minorities and securize the actors (1996b : 203). We seem thus invited to reflect in our Human Rights' problematic on the elaboration of adequate forums through which the tackling of diverse problems can be efficiently operationalized. To do so, sociological analysis of the different contexts is necessary but also a more general reflection upon the relations between the forums, the stakes, and the relevant social orders.
Square Eight : Orders
We
will not dwell on that square here as we have extensively dealt with the
different social orders, their related forms of regulation and their related
logics in Part I. Let us just recall that in order efficiently to put into
forms Human Rights problematics in different cultural contexts, the proposed
forms should be adapted to the orders valorised in those different cultural
contexts. Approaching for example Human Rights from the point of view of
imposed order in societies valorising the negotiated or accepted order turns
out to be problematic, if not completely inefficient. Furthermore, next to
the specific contexts of action, the purpose of the action itself should
be taken into account in the choice to valorise an approach in the terms
of one order or another, or in the choice of their articulation. In the long
run for example it appears more appropriate to build on the accepted order
and its correlated habitus. In short term operations, an imposed order approach,
to maintain peace for example, may reveal itself necessary.
Square Nine : Stakes
The stakes are what gives
meaning to the game. These stakes can be material as well as immaterial,
just like the resources we have encountered on Square Two. These stakes can
also be more or less explicit or implicit. In the social game, strategies
and tactics trying to hide the players' aims are commonplace. Furthermore,
the actors themselves may not always pursue some very clearly defined aims.
The expected gains also need not to be immediate but could be differed in
time. Stakes bring us back to the reflections developed around strategies
and tactics. What are the aims we pursue ? What is at stake ? Is it the well
being of our generation, of future generations, of individuals, of communities
? Is it the well being of a more local or of a more global community ? Is
it a more material or immaterial well being? Is it life in dignity, peace
? Is a life in dignity a life in which a minimum of material conditions are
fulfilled ? Is it a life which is recognized by the community or the communities
of belonging and which can actively participate in the community's or the
communities' life or lives ? Furthermore, this square reminds us that in
the social game different players want to get different things. In our Human
Rights' thought we must not forget to take into consideration that there
may be very diverse political, economical, sociological, cultural etc ...
stakes.
Square Ten : Rules of the
Game
By
patiently playing our Human Rights' jeu de l'oie we may little by
little be able to work out the Rules of an intercultural Human Rights' game.
On the global level this may help us to operationalize our Human Rights'
Community and to deepen our understanding of it. The patient advancement,
step by step, from square to square may permit us, on the one hand to help
shedding light on partial Human Rights' games which make up (or could make
up) the global game, thus enabling their articulation, and, on the other
to take us deeper into the mechanisms (those already existing and those still
to be invented) necessary to understand and to play the global intercultural
Human Rights' game.
We
come now to the end of our Part II. We have in Part I outlined a possible
intercultural meeting place for Human Rights' practice : the forum of our
Common Humanities. We have in Part II focused on our actual meeting and sharing
by presenting our Human Community as a frame for intercultural Human Rights'
practice. By doing so we have advocated an emphasis on Praxis
rather than on System in our Human Rights' thought. This led
us to propose an operationalization of the concept of Human Community in
legal theory through the perspective of game. Van de KERCHOVE's and OST's
paradigm of game already provided us with a praxis and plurality oriented
frame for thought, although it still staid a systemic one. But
to really be able to think in terms of Community we have advocated the necessity
to completely leave a systemic approach in favour of a Communitarian,
living approach to Law. The Jeu de l'oie seemed to provide
us with the frame for such an approach. Its perspective is the one of the
actor. Each square reminds us of one of the relevant aspects of life he is
knotting together in his person and action in particular ways
in particular situations in order to play the legal game, the
jeu de lois. The Jeu de l'oie thus permitted us to approach
the Human Rights' problematic in an ordered and although dynamic and plural
way. By starting on the actual practices of the actors it may permit to elaborate
the most adequate rules for a working Human Rights'
Game.
But in order to play together
our Human Rights' Game, we need some common horizon which provides it with
sense. We will know, in Part III, try to approach this common though plural
horizon for intercultural Human Rights' practice through the concept of
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights.
Let us start by meditating the famous parable of the elephant in the dark
of Djalâl ud-Dîn RUMI :
Hindus had brought an elephant ; they exhibited it in a dark house.
Several people entered, one by one, in the dark, to see it.
Not being able to see it with their eyes, they touched it with their hands.
One put his hand on the trunk ; he said : This creature is like a water pipe.
Another touched its ear : it felt to him like a fan.
Having gripped its leg, another one declared : The elephant has the shape of a pillar.
After having laid his hand on its back, another one said : To say the truth, this elephant is like a throne.
Also, each time that one heard a description of the elephant, he understood it according to the part he had touched.
Their affirmations varied according to what they had perceived : one called it dal, the other alîf .
If each of them had had a candle, their sayings would not have differed.
The eye of perception is as limited as the palm of the hand which could not comprehend the totality (of the elephant).
The eye of the sea is one thing, the foam is another ; leave behind the foam and look with the eye of the sea.
Night and day, coming from the sea, the flakes of foam are moving ; you see the foam, not the sea. How strange this is !
We collide with each other like small boats ; our eyes are blinded ; and yet the water is clear.
Oh you, who fell asleep in the ship of the body, you have seen the water ; contemplate the Water of the water.
Water has a Water which pushes it, spirit a Spirit which is calling it. -35-
Until now we have approached
the intercultural Human Rights' problematic in a way corresponding to the
first part of the parable. We have considered that Human Rights
are something like the elephant in the dark. To get an idea of what they
could be, we have advocated the necessity to acknowledge the existence of
different perspectives, and thus also the relativity of our own perspective.
We have emphasized that the fact that we have for example grabbed the
trunk of Human Rights should not induce us in the error to think
that Human Rights are a water pipe, nor to negate a priori the point
of view of those who have touched the ears or legs
of Human Rights. We have advocated the necessity in order to get a more complete
picture of Human Rights to acknowledge the complementarity of perspectives.
Thus, have we argued, we could maybe build up, through the articulation of
partial perspectives, an intercultural and more complete picture of Human
Rights.We have in Parts I and II given account of a praxis of Human Rights,
constituted of a never ending process of dialoguing, acting, reflecting,
etc, paralleling what the people of the above story could do : touch the
elephant, get a mental picture of it, exchange their views among them, and
thus little by little come to know what the real elephant looks like.
We
can say, that what we have done in Parts I and II, is to engage in a
dianthropological (dia - anthropos -logos) praxis
of Human Rights. Indeed, as we have already defined it, the dialogue
is a journey through different logics. But we have not confined ourselves
to logics only, but have also included practices in reflecting upon intercultural
Human Rights. Further, we have seen that logics are determined by different
standpoints, perspectives, which are underlaid by different myths to which
dialogue provides an entry. We have thus put into practice the fundamental
demand of legal anthropology, which is always to bring back the legal
discourses and practices to the systems of thought and to the logics which
generate them (LE ROY 1993b : 235). That is the reason why I have chosen
to speak of dianthropological praxis in order to characterize
our demarche which is an outlook on Human Rights as emerging from the different
anthropologies of our Common Humanities, and an emphasizing of a shared Human
Rights Praxis, a practice sustained by theory and a theory sustained by practice,
embedded in our Human Community.
But for the moment, we have
not embedded our dianthropological endeavour itself in a broader horizon
which could provide it with meaning and common perspectives in which all
cultures could share. We have staid at an analytical level without yet providing
an outlook on a possible synthesis of the insights that could be gained through
dianthropological endeavour. We have not yet come to the second part of the
parable. We have not yet left the domain of logos. Our dianthropology
may have led us to the mythoi underlying the different cultural
topoi. But in our journey we have nevertheless remained in the domain
of logos and have not yet dealt with the intercultural mythos
in which our demarche may be embedded. We have remained in the realm of what
can be perceived by our limited eye of perception, by the eye
of the foam (what this exactly means will become clearer in Chapter
V). In order to access a possible intercultural founding myth of intercultural
Human Rights' Praxis, a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights (in upper-case),
it may be fruitful to complement dianthropological praxis as developed until
now, social sciences' dianthropological praxis by a spiritual
dianthropological praxis characterized by the aim of spiritual traditions
to take us beyond the realm of logos, beyond anthropologos, through
a spiritual praxis emphasizing direct experience of what we are, and thus
giving a more synthesized, but also more mythical,
account of what we are than a social sciences' approach based
on analysis through the logos. We will thus in this Part, in order
to be able to approach our possible intercultural myth of Dianthropological
Praxis of Human Rights, engage in a dialogue with spiritual traditions.
In
Chapter V, we will reflect upon the possible enrichments of our Human Rights'
thought in the intercultural context through dialogue with spiritual traditions.
We will try to see in which way this dialogue could permit us to enrich our
picture of Man in order to help us to think of an intercultural
universality of the Human, which could permit to found an
intercultural universality of Human Rights and thus provide us
with a shared horizon for our common praxis of Human Rights. Further, Chapter
V will also provide us with a bridge towards Chapter VI, in which we will
dwell rather in the realm of mythos than of logos. Indeed,
building on the insights gained in Chapter V, we will try in Chapter VI to
identify a possible intercultural grounding myth, Dianthropological Praxis
of Human Rights, which could provide a shared horizon for action, and a terrain
for growth to the Common Humanities' Human Rights' Praxis in the Human Community.
Chapter V : A Dialogue with Spiritual Traditions in order to Enrich our
Picture of Man
Nasrudin started haranguing the people on the market place. Hey ! You ! Do you want knowledge without pains, truth without the false, success without effort, progress without sacrifice ?
In the wink of an eye, an immense crowd had assembled around him. And all shouted : Yes ! yes!
Perfect ! said the Mulla. I only wanted
to get an idea. If I ever discover such a thing, you can count on me not
to hide it from you. (SHAH 1989: 125) -36-
This little story should warn
us not to believe that the spiritual traditions will be able to provide us
with a ready-to-wear conception of the Human, with the
truth about Human nature, which should impose itself in our Human Rights'
thought. But we should also be aware of a different danger facing us when
dealing with spiritual traditions. It is the danger to dismiss what those
traditions could teach us, before we have even taken the time to have a closer
look at them because they appear too strange to us at first sight.
In
my opinion, our conception of spirituality to often suffers of the
encompassing of the contrary. We either construct it, positively,
as all-encompassing, absolute in opposition to our rational or scientific
knowledge which we think of as partial and relative. Or we construct it,
negatively, as emotional, irrational, unscientific, unproven in opposition
to our rational, scientific, proven knowledge. I think that here again genuine
dialogical dialogue is necessary if we want to be able to understand the
spiritual traditions' teachings and to fertilize our Human Rights' thought
by them. In order to enable genuine dialogue and understanding, I will thus
in the following pages not try to present spiritual traditions from an exterior
point of view. I will rather try to draw on the testimony provided by spiritual
masters of different traditions, in order to enable us to get a glance from
within. As in intercultural dialogue, if a dialogical approach is necessary
to enable us to get in contact with those traditions, it does not end there.
As we have argued in relation to our Common Humanities, the dialogical approach
aiming at understanding is only the first necessary step which could lead
us to creative dialogue, a dialogue of mutual interfecundation
and enrichment, a dialogue which from acknowledgement of the existing becomes
creation of the (commonly) possible. It is my firm conviction that dialogue
among spiritual traditions and among them and secular traditions on the problem
of human nature can turn out to be very fruitful in the context
of a search for an intercultural universality, a mestizaje, of Human
Rights.
As
my own experience has made me more familiar with the Indian teachings (Buddhist
and Hinduist) and with AIVANHOV's Christian esotericism (which also draws
on traditions like the Jewish Kabbala or the Indian Yoga systems) my reasoning
will largely rely on this perspective. My knowledge is thus very partial
and my intent is rather to invite through this chapter to a dialogue with
spiritual traditions, than to propose any final conclusions. I hope that
this chapter will be able to familiarize the reader to some extent with the
way some spiritual traditions tackle the problem of human nature.
I further hope that it will succeed to show the interest which could lay
in enriching our Human Rights' theory by spiritual perspectives.
It is, of course, self-evident that the proposed approach to the dialogue
with spiritual traditions is only one possible proposition stemming from
my personal experience, which must be enriched by criticisms and contributions
from different perspectives and by the contributions from other traditions.
To
me, fecundation of Human Rights' thought through dialogue with the spiritual
traditions seems relevant as reflection upon Human Rights to a large extent
relies upon reflection upon human nature and its universality.
ROSENBAUM (1981 : 25) notes that most philosophers agree on the fundamental
character of the issue of human nature in Human Rights' thought.
And he remarks (1981 : 25) that :
In basing human rights on human nature
or personhood, one must have a defensible concept of the latter; otherwise,
human rights will be arbitrarily defined, with no inevitable link having
been established between the morality of being human and the facts of
existence.
It
thus seems interesting to try to outline what the spiritual traditions could
contribute to the building of a defensible concept of human nature,
which could turn out to be useful for intercultural Human Rights' thought.
Let us remark with ROSENBAUM
(1981 : 33) that, although there are not many of them, there are a few recent
philosophers inclined to found human rights at the cosmic or spiritual levels.
He writes (1981 : 33-34) :
Some philosophers (...) do speak of human reality as profoundly as they would of a god, whereas others in this perspective are unable to separate morality from broader religious and metaphysical considerations.
(...) Although the neo-Kantian view of natural law may be an attempt to circumvent the modern bias against absolutes, it relies upon a metaphysical, or even theological, conception of universal order which ultimately authenticates human rights, values and purposes.
It is in this sense that natural-law metaphysics
is closely aligned with religious conceptions of human rights, as has been
illustrated by the favorable comparisons of the spirit and purpose of human
rights with the basic principles of certain religious traditions in respect
of human nature and human destiny.
So
let us now engage in a dialogue on human nature with the spiritual
traditions. We will do so, not in order to discover some natural law, but
rather to open perspectives in order to contribute to the elaboration of
a picture of man, which could be shared by all cultures and give rise to
an intercultural myth of Human Rights able to sustain our intercultural
Communitarian Human Rights' Praxis.
In
the following pages I will try to show in what an enrichment of our
picture of Man by the spiritual traditions could consist in.
I will start by presenting what I call spiritual traditions and
by giving a first glance of their approach to the Human and of their possible
contributions to Human Rights' theory (I). I will then try to show one possible
way of opening up our notion of dignity by those insights, in order to enable
its transition from a localised universalism into a homeomorphic
concept which could make sense across several cultures (II) . But before
doing so, it may be appropriate to listen to a Tibetan Buddhist master's,
SOGYAL RINPOCHE's, advice to those wanting to enter into contact with
spirituality (1995 : 131) :
Read the great spiritual books of all
the traditions, come to some understanding of what the masters might mean
by liberation and enlightenment, and find out which approach to absolute
reality really attracts and suits you most. Exercise in your search as much
discernment as you can ; the spiritual path demands more intelligence, more
sober understanding, more subtle powers of discrimination than any other
discipline, because the highest truth is at stake. Use your common sense
at every moment. Come to the path as humorously aware as possible of the
baggage you will be bringing with you : your lacks, fantasies, failings,
and projections. Blend, with a soaring awareness of what your true nature
might be, a down-to-earth and level-headed humility, and a clear appreciation
of where you are on your spiritual journey and what still remains to be
understood and accomplished.
I. Spiritual Traditions
and the Human
Let us start by presenting
what we understand under spiritual traditions and how we think
that they could enrich the Human Rights' discussion (1) before having a closer
look on their outlook on Man (2).
1. What are Spiritual
Traditions and what Could they Contribute to the Human Rights' Discussion
?
I
will use the term spiritual tradition in order to designate all
traditions aiming at an understanding of Man and of his transformation in
order to permit him to live in harmony with himself, his fellows, his
environment, the world, the cosmos, and, in the theist traditions, with God
or the Gods. I thus do not limit the term spiritual tradition
either to an institutionalised form of belief, nor to a religion which would
be characterized by a belief in God or Gods. Furthermore, I would like to
emphasize that spiritual traditions have an exoteric and an esoteric aspect.
Their exoteric aspect can be understood as their form, their esoteric aspect
as that which is put into forms, the essence of the teachings. It is the
realisation of the essence of the teachings and not the mere observance of
the exterior forms which has produced what are considered as the great sages
of the world, the great spiritual masters, the great initiates. KALOU RINPOCHE
(1993 : 32) an important contemporary master of Tibetan Buddhism said :
All traditions, Christian, Hindu, Jewish,
Muslim, Buddhist ..., teach that the comprehension of what we are on the
most profound level is the essential point : this comprehension of the nature
of the spirit enlightens from within the teachings of all traditions. In
each of them, whoever reaches the intimate comprehension of the mind and
makes its direct experience, ends up with an essential vision, without any
common measure to the one he could have had before this direct experience.
The comprehension of the nature of the mind is the key which opens the
comprehension of all teachings. It sheds light on what we are, on the nature
of all our experiences and reveals the most profound form of love and
compassion. -37-
We
can put those words in a Christian perspective through the sayings of Omraam
Mikhaël AIVANHOV, in which it becomes very clear that the core of spiritual
traditions is not constituted by their forms, which are variable, but by
the content these forms seek to express. He says (AIVANHOV 1994 : 11 and
26) :
Since millenniums human beings have taken the habit to dwell on forms and the appearance of things and to leave aside their content and their meaning. This is also what they have done with the Sacred books which also have a form, a content and a meaning. The form, the narrative is for ordinary people ; the moral, symbolic content is for the disciples who try to deepen and to live it ; whereas the spiritual meaning is for the Initiates who know how to interpret it. (...)
Every form, that means every thing or being which
is born must die and must leave its place to others. Only, the spirit which
has no beginning has no end, and it is him who gets successively incarnated
in ever new forms. God did not provide form with eternity ; form is friable,
ephemeral, it cannot stand the test of time. Only the principle, the spirit,
which pertains to the realm of the divine, is indestructible, eternal.
-38-
And Shri RAMAKRISHNA a very
influential Hindu master of the last century illustrates in my opinion very
well, that spiritual endeavour is before all self-discovery. Although speaking
in terms of God, he sees God not as something remote from the Human, but
rather as its very essence. He says (in HERBERT 1972 : 464) :
A man who attains true Wisdom does not
see God as a remote being, he does not feel Him outside of himself, but in
himself, in the depths of his soul. God is in all, those who seek Him find
Him in themselves. -39-
I
hope this quotations have permitted to describe what we will designate as
spiritual traditions. Through these quotations, spiritual traditions appear
not as mere systems of ideas, symbols, rites etc, but more essentially as
ways leading us to an understanding of ourselves and to the realisation of
our true nature, may we call it the mind, human
nature, God or still something else. They are thus closely
connected to our research on the universal in Man, which could
constitute a horizon for a shared Human Rights' Praxis. Their original
contribution is that they can lead us beyond the realm of pure logos by
permitting us to enter into a direct relation to our life and its realm(s)
- or at least do they permit us to enter into dialogue with people who have
directly experienced life through spiritual training. Indeed,
spiritual traditions can be seen as the paths, the ways to our own (human,
divine, living, cosmic, or whatever it may be called) nature.
They can be seen as the mirrors which can permit us to discover our real
face. KALOU RINPOCHE (1993 : 46) says :
It is only if we are able to make the detour
of using a mirror that we will be able to see our face. As the eye needs
this particular object to see itself, the mind needs a particular means which
plays the role of the mirror in which it can discover its true face : this
means is the dharma as it is transmitted to us by a spiritual guide. It is
in our relation to the teachings and to this spiritual friend or to this
guide that the mind will little by little be able to waken up to its true
nature and will finally go beyond the initial paradox, by discovering another
mode of knowing. This discovery is made in diverse practices, called practices
of meditation. (...) -40-
As
people are different, as the conditions in which they live are different,
there are numerous different mirrors, numerous different spiritual
traditions. We should never forget this fact while engaging in intercultural
dialogue on Human Rights. Even if there may be a universal human
nature which could provide us with a shared horizon for Human Rights'
Praxis, we must never forget that this universal human nature
must limit itself to the role of horizon and permit different ways of living
under it. As the DALAI-LAMA (1994 : 84) says :
(...) to respond to the diverse needs of
beings and to satisfy their different dispositions, aspirations and tendencies,
a great variety of philosophies, religions and spiritual traditions are needed.
Considering the huge diversity of needs of all, it would appear very difficult
that solely one religion could suffice. The more there are spiritual paths,
the better it is ! At the same time, it is certain that the different beliefs
can coexist harmoniously, as the fundamental, universal ethic is an important
place for agreement. It will suffice that those practising those different
paths learn to know each other better and that they benefit of what the other
religions teach them in order to improve their personal practice.
-41-
I
would even extend this invitation of mutual dialogue and enrichment between
spiritual traditions to a dialogue between religious and secular traditions.
But what seems paramount to me is that we start acknowledging the richness
of diversity, in order to be little by little really able to appreciate it.
There is not one truth, which of course we hold, and which we have to share
with all the others. Most of the time this missionary attitude leads us to
try to convert the others to our point of view, or even to impose our point
of view on them - as we think - for their sake. But in any way this attitude
leads us to not taking the testimony of the other's life seriously, to negate
him in a way, and to preclude thus right from the start any genuine dialogue.
Mutual exchange and enrichment thus turns out to be impossible. Maybe we
should meditate Swâmi VIVEKANANDA's words reflecting upon a universal
religion when we reflect upon a universal Human Rights' system
(1972 : 374-375) :
You know that there are minds of different kinds. One can be a materialist who believes in common sense and in earth to earth realities ; one can not be interested in forms and in ceremonies ; one can demand solid facts, which resound and which speak to intelligence, and can not be contented with anything else. There are also Puritans and Muslims who do not tolerate in their places of worship neither statutes nor images. Very well, but there may be such other man who is more of an artist and needs great artistic deployment, beautiful lines, gracious curves, (...) ; his mind conceives God by these exterior forms just as your mind conceives Him through intelligence. There is also the man of devotion, whose soul frantically cries out for God ; his sole idea is to adore God and to sing His praises. Further there is the philosopher, who stays at some distance and makes fun of the others. 'What foolishness, he thinks, what strange ways to conceive of God !'
They can laugh of each other, but each of them
has his place in the world. All these different minds, all these diverse
types are necessary. If there should ever be a universal religion, it will
have to be vast and broad enough to provide all these minds with what they
need. It must give to the philosopher the force of philosophy, to the worshipper
the heart of the devotee, to the ritualist all that the most marvellous symbolism
can provide for, to the poet as much feeling as he can absorb, and still
something else. To build a religion vast enough, we will have to come back
to the time where all religions started and embrace them all. -42-
So
if we ever want come to a universal picture of Man, we seem invited
to conceive it vast enough to keep a place for the aspirations of all humans.
The acknowledging of the diversity of approaches to the Human seems to be
a fundamental requirement in this endeavour and seems underlined by at least
some representatives of spiritual traditions. Universality thus does not
seem to be by its nature against diversity. The acknowledgement
of diversity does not preclude a search for universality - it only precludes
the search for a uniformizing universality built on the principle
of subtraction. But it does not preclude the research for a universality
built on the principle of addition and acknowledging the worth of plurality.
One will never be able to reduce the various traditions and world views to
a uniform tradition or world view. At the best it may be possible to come
to a united tradition or world view in the image of our Human Rights' Community.
In order to think pluralism in the domain of universals,
intercultural dialogue may again turn out to be fruitful. A religion's
universality for instance must not necessarily rely upon the uniform submission
of all to it, as we tend to think in a Christian perspective. In Indian thought
for example, where the differences of characters and the necessity of adapted
spiritual paths for each are an accepted fact, different yogas, or spiritual
paths, coexist and complement each other. In each of them realisation of
God is sought in a different way. There is for example Karma yoga or yoga
of disinterested action, Bhakti yoga or yoga of devotion,
Jnâna yoga or yoga of knowledge, etc ... (see VIVEKANANDA
1970, 1972). But us we have seen through the quotations, if the mirrors,
the forms are numerous, the underlying reality is nevertheless seen as one.
Maybe should we think of a
universality of Human Rights on similar lines. Forms are important in order
to render reality intelligible to us, and to enable us to make sense out
of it. Without a window, without a standpoint, without a perspective we could
not see anything - we would be lost. Limitation is necessary to our perception
and to our life. But these perspectives do not mean radical subjectivism
and relativism. It may be possible to see the same thing differently. And
it may be a big step forwards to start to understand that at first sight
contradictory statements and views can in fact turn out to be complementary.
Nevertheless this does not entail that all views are right, just because
they have been uttered by someone. If there can exist different correct views
on an object as the result of different perspectives, there can also exist
blurred views, incorrect views of it, not to speak of fantasies ! If a man
having touched the ears of the elephant constructs them as wings and concludes
that elephants can fly, he is wrong - Dumbo (Disney's flying elephant) exists
... but only in our imagination. Views on the Human can thus be correct but
partial, but they can also be wrong. This is why it is necessary to have
a possibility of testing the proposed views. Contrary to what one may think,
the spiritual traditions are very concerned with testing their teachings,
with providing tools for testing and realizing them. They are not just opinions
on human nature. They are a methodic enquiry on human
nature (SHAH 1994 : 54, KRISHNA 1994 : 2 ff). Like any enquiry or any
science, they have their methods which can have their advantages and their
drawbacks. It seems thus important to me that spiritual traditions engage
in mutual dialogue and in dialogue with normal science in order
to shed clearer and clearer light on human nature. Their main
contribution can be in my opinion their stock of lived experience through
which deep insights on the human have emerged and still emerge. Their main
draw-back to be overcome is maybe their very often strong dogmatism which
does not allow the questioning of fundamental cornerstones of their belief.
We should thus maybe, as VIVEKANANDA says go straight to the facts.
He writes
(1972 : 136) :
There are certain religious facts which
must be perceived just like facts in material science, and it is on these
facts that religion will be built. (...) The sages of the world only have
the right to tell us that they have analysed their mind, that they have made
such and such observation, and that if we proceed alikely we also will believe,
but not before. That is all that there is in religion. -43-
Let us note that we should
not understand religion here in its traditional sense but rather in the sense
of an endeavour in self-knowledge, which can of course be seen, or which
can turn out to be, search for knowledge of the world or of
God. It seems that the different spiritual traditions, as spiritual
practices which constitute different methods for the attainment
of spiritual objectives, for verifying the doctrines formulated by prophets
and sages, and for experiencing the Transcendent, as Gopi KRISHNA
(1994 : 2) writes about Indian Yoga, have lead to the experience of similar,
universal facts about the human all over the world. Nevertheless
they have weighed differently different aspects of the experience of the
human and have expressed this experience in multiple ways. Our challenge
may be to come now to a mutual enrichment of all these traditions, to an
exchange of perspectives on the experiences of human nature.
This may permit, maybe not to replace the old concepts, but at least to
complement them by a federative concept in which all different traditions
could share.
I
hope to have allowed through this short presentation to provide a glimpse
on the potential interest of spiritual traditions for the Human Rights' dialogue,
especially in what concerns the problem of the human nature.
The time seems therefore ripe
to engage in interdisciplinary dialogue with them on the Human.
To sum up I think we could expect this dialogue to be fruitful from two points
of view. First of all reflection on the spiritual teachings by contrasting
them with normal science, and among themselves may enable us
to crystallize what is universal in Man. It may permit us to get closer to
the underlying human reality. The dialogical approach permits
us to do so, without necessarily having to undergo ourselves a spiritual
training. Of course we will in that way not acquire first hand experience,
and will not go beyond the realm of logos. But we cannot all become
spiritual masters. And this is not even necessary. We are not all top scientists
and engineers and nevertheless we daily use their findings without often
having the slightest clue of how the things we use work. Generally speaking,
for example, we trust doctors who want to cure us, teachers who instruct
us etc, and experience may confirm that we are right in doing so. In the
same way it is not necessary to all become specialists in spiritual matters.
But we should at least develop a common culture, a basic understanding of
what spirituality is about. This could help us to discriminate the
true from the fake and may permit us to build up
the necessary trust in the yet unknown, to be able to engage in mutually
enriching dialogue. In our enlightened tradition this trust can, in my eyes,
best be built through a rational analysis of what spiritual traditions propose.
We should not accept anything without checking. But at the same time we should
not reject anything without checking. To dismiss a priori the teachings of
often millenary traditions, which still today influence the lives of millions
of people in the name of a Western science or rationality would seem to me
- actually, taking into account the immense Asian context, probably the majority
of humankind - not only intolerant but foolish. I do believe that the teachings
of spiritual traditions can enrich the Human Rights' debate through their
insights on the basic structures and processes which make up the Human and
which stem from lived experiences reaching to the most profound realms of
the Human.
This anchoring in praxis brings
us to the second enrichment that interdisciplinary dialogue with spiritual
traditions may provide. Although deeply embedded in Human nature
the spiritual traditions are nevertheless not abstract. On the contrary,
as ways of living, they are integral part of their cultural environment -
and we have seen in Part I to what extent social organisation and world views
are linked. I thus think that by going to the common ground of spiritual
traditions we find ourselves at the base of homeomorphic equivalents in what
concerns the most basic and fundamental aspects of human life. This may permit
us to work out not so much a universal image of Man in the classical sense,
but rather a shared picture of Man. This would be a picture of
Man which could be shared by all human beings. It would provide a certain
global outlook on the human but which would at the same time
send each culture back to its own conceptions. It would be a homeomorphic
picture of Man rather than a universal one. It would permit rootedness in
the local, open to cross-fertilisation through the
global. Let us now move on and look at Man through the prism
of the spiritual traditions.
2. Man Seen through the
Prism of the Spiritual Traditions
SOGYAL RINPOCHE (1995 : 56) relates the enlightenment of the BUDDHA as told by the Vietnamese master Tich Nhat Hanh :
Gautama felt as though a prison which
had confined him for thousands of lifetimes had broken open. Ignorance had
been the jailkeeper. Because of ignorance, his mind had been obscured, just
like the moon and stars hidden by the storm or clouds. Clouded by endless
waves of deluded thoughts, the mind had falsely divided reality into subject
and object, self and others, existence and non-existence, birth and death,
and from these discriminations arose wrong views - the prisons of feelings,
craving, grasping and becoming. The suffering of birth, old age, sickness,
an death only made the prison walls thicker. The only thing to do was to
seize the jailkeeper and see his true face. The jailkeeper was ignorance....
Once the jailkeeper was gone, the jail would disappear and never be rebuilt
again. (SOGYAL RINPOCHE 1995 : 56)
We
see here that Buddhism, like other spiritual traditions, insists on the fact
that what we perceive as the Human being, a body, its intellect, its emotions,
are only one limited aspect of the Human in its totality. Human nature is
not seen as confined in the individual - one could maybe even say in the
spiritual traditions' perspective that it is the individual who is confined
in human nature. The individual is only seen as the partial
reflection of a much broader reality. Through patient work man may become
more and more Man by gradually discovering his broader reality. And by doing
so he may get more and more aware of his link with life, or the cosmos, or
nature or God - however he conceives of existence. What we cling to as our
individuality is seen by the Indian spiritual traditions as a mere delusion.
It is a limitation of our true being due to ignorance. According to the spiritual
traditions we are always Man or/and God or/and the Cosmos, but our ignorance
hinders us to recognize this. That is why we have to unroot ignorance in
order to recognize our real being, and to get freed from our limited prison
through this knowledge. This understanding may turn out to be relevant in
the Human Rights' discussion as it can permit, as we will develop further
(p 94 ff), to enrich our notion of human dignity which lies at the core of
our Human Rights' thought. Our dignity must not necessarily be seen as relying
exclusively on our personal individuality, somehow seen as confined in us.
It can also be seen as the consequence of the fact that the human being is
a manifestation of a much broader reality linked to all of humanity, to all
living beings, to the whole universe or if one conceives of God to God. Ramana
MAHARSHI, a Hindu sage of this century, characterized by the fact that he
always led back all questions to the fundamental question Who am I
? said (1993 : 417-418) :
Everyone on this earth is the Self, which is infinite.
(...) Nobody is remote from the Self. Consequently everybody is in the Self, and thus realised. (...)
The realisation thus consists in rejecting the false idea, that one is not realised. Realisation is not something new to be acquired. As it is permanent, it must exist of all time. Otherwise it does not have any value.
From the very moment on where the mistaken idea
I am the body or I am not realised is dissipated,
only remains the supreme Consciousness, the Self to which the name of realisation
is given to satisfy the level of understanding of ordinary men. But to tell
the truth, realisation is eternal, it exists since always, at present and
here and now. In the end realisation comes to eliminating ignorance and nothing
else. -44-
It
becomes clear now what RUMI meant in his parable of the elephant in the dark
with the eye of the Sea and the eye of the foam.
The eye of the sea is the enlightened eye of the Self, to use Ramana MAHARSHI's
terminology. The eye of the foam is the deluded eye of our limited self.
Spiritual traditions thus acknowledge the existence of a state of ignorance
and of a state of knowledge - the passage from one to the other being
enlightenment. But as MAHARSHI notes this passage is only elimination of
our misconceptions about our Selves. It is not the acquiring of some new
knowledge but the realisation of an already present knowledge. This insight
can be relevant in Human Rights' thought as it can put into perspective the
idea of an inherent dignity of Man. Dignity could be seen as the result of
every human being's potential for self-knowledge, or rather for Self-knowledge,
which seems deeply embedded in his very being which is the Self, and which
seems universal as all human beings share in it.
But this idea of the passage
from a state of ignorance about our human nature to a state of knowledge
about it, can also lead us to more pragmatic considerations on possible ideals
which could orient our living together in our Human Community. Indeed, one
often has the picture of enlightenment happening out of the blue - a total
change from a state of complete ignorance to a state of complete knowing.
But this is not how things happen. And by the way, that is the reason why
spiritual traditions do exist. In order to attain enlightenment patient work
on oneself is necessary. This work leads to physical, psychological and spiritual
change. We become more sensitive to more subtle realities of life. Our view
of it gets clearer. We start to feel more space in us. We start to increasingly
feel our link to the rest of creation. Little by little a process of opening
up occurs. This opening up permits the light of the spirit to
shine. Thus our whole human existence can be seen as a process, a struggling,
between two poles : one attracting us to a never ending opening up, the other
to the clinging to our limitations. The spiritual traditions intend to lead
us to the pole of opening up, of enlightenment. That is why at the basis
of their teachings they all have the rule : not I, you. Omraam
Mikhaël AIVANHOV conceptualises these two opposite poles of the Human
being as a superior individuality and an inferior
personality. Personality is the egoistic, limited, human pole
of the Human being. Individuality is the altruistic, unlimited, divine pole
of the Human being :
Since the thousands of years where men have studied themselves in order to know the structure of their psychical life, they have imagined numerous modes of division. (...) Whatever the adopted point of view, it is always truthful, it depends under which angle the things are observed.
To simplify the question, we will say that the human being is a perfect unity, but that this unity is polarised. This means that it manifests itself into two directions, through two different aspects. Man is made of two natures : the inferior nature and the superior nature, which have the same faculties to think, to feel and to act, but in two opposite directions. I have called these two natures personality and individuality. (AIVANHOV 1984 : 23-24)
-45-
For the sake of simplicity
we will keep up with this terminology where individuality designates
the human pole of opening up, personality the human pole of clinging
to one's limitations. It appears thus from what we have said above that the
two notions of knowledge, or Wisdom, and of Love are profoundly intertwined.
Knowledge, presupposes opening up, broadening our perspective. But how could
we broaden our perspective if we do not manage to progressively abandon the
idea of I ? In order to know, we must open ourselves up to others.
We must learn to think : not I, you . Thus to pass from personality
to individuality, from ignorance to knowledge, we need to learn to love.
Swâmi VIVEKANANDA said about Love (1972 : 352-353) :
The device of all well-being, of all moral good is : Not me, but you. (...) Forget about yourselves ; this is the first lesson to be learned, may you be religious or atheistic, agnostic or vedantist, Christian or Muslim. The great lesson which is evident for all, is the destruction of the little self and the construction of the Real Self.
Two forces have been at work side by side and parallelly. One says me, the other says not me. (...) from one end to the other of creation, this two forces work side by side. Each time you find one, you also find the other. One is egoism, the other altruism. One is acquisition, the other renouncement. One takes, the other gives.
(...) Is there anybody who can deny that this
love, this not-me, this renunciation is the sole positive power
in the world ? The other is only a badly oriented use of the power of love
(...) A man who murders another one has maybe been pushed to this act by
the love for his child. His love has limited itself to a little child and
millions of other beings populating the universe have been excluded.
Nevertheless, limited or unlimited, it is always the same love. -46-
It
thus seems that the spiritual traditions invite us in the Human Rights context
to reflect upon human nature and its universality in relation
to the concepts of Wisdom (knowledge) and Love. We will develop these insights
further in Chapter VI where we will also develop the important idea of Peace.
For the moment let us just remark that our gradual opening up may lead us
step by step to the recognition of the fundamental interconnectedness of
things, by revealing us the broader nature of ourselves.
Nevertheless if spiritual
traditions can provide us, as we could see, with potentially fruitful insights
on human nature in the frame of Human Rights' thought, we must nevertheless
note that Human Rights' theory must complement the reflections upon the
individuality of Man (according to AIVANHOV's terminology) which
can contribute to the elaboration of a concept of universality of Human Rights,
by taking into account human personality. We will try to do so
in the next part by reflecting on ways to mutually fecundate the western
notion of individual dignity, which demands respect for the concrete individual,
with the kind of dignity having its roots in human individuality
as presented here. Indeed the aim of spiritual traditions is not to organize
social life but to further personal self-realisation. It will therefore be
necessary to engage into a dialogue on how the spiritual traditions' insights
could be fruitfully integrated in the Human Rights' Context. I will try in
Chapter VI to make a first proposition for this dialogue by proposing a picture
of how we could constitute an underlying myth for intercultural Human Rights'
Praxis. Indeed, as lawyers we cannot content ourselves with dreaming of a
world peopled only by individuals and not by persons
and propose a completely utopian model. We must try to propose models which
are viable in our concrete world. Let us not forget that what we advocate
in this thesis, is heterotopia, displacement in this world, not utopia,
displacement in an unreal elsewhere. In this perspective, I think that the
role of spiritual traditions in Human Rights' theory could be to contribute
to the building of a picture of Man which could firmly root Human Rights
in our human existence. Through their roots in millennary praxis, renewed
generation after generation, I firmly believe that they can help us to
consolidate our reflection on Human Rights by enriching our classical natural
law's approaches as well as our legal positivism's approaches.
For the moment we have especially
worked out two aspects of Man in a spiritual perspective : his constitution
in two poles and its dynamism resulting from the struggle between those two
poles. We have also said a few words on how these insights could enrich our
notion of dignity. Let us now deepen this endeavour. By doing so, we will
try to enable the concretization of these spiritual insights into a notion
which could be operationalized in the legal field, by stressing again the
importance of the individual in the world as we conceive it in the western
tradition, and which seemed to get a little dissolved in our holistic spiritual
approaches. This endeavour may also permit us to open up our Western notion
of dignity, the basis of our Human Rights' thought, to a more homeomorphic
image of Man. We will thus try to make a Western contribution to the building
of a shared homeomorphic concept of Man, which will, as we will see, necessarily
have to be of a plural and dynamic, and thus Communitarian nature.
II. Enriching the Notion of Dignity by the Spiritual Teachings : Towards a Homeomorphic and
Communitarian Picture
of Man
The notion of Human Dignity,
as already noted, seems paramount in order to be able to found and to put
into practice Human Rights. It seems to me closely linked to the spiritual
nature of Man and I thus think that it can be beneficially enriched and fostered
by the contributions spiritual traditions can make to its understanding.
MASSINI-CORREAS in his article
El pensamiento contamporaneo acerco de los derechos humanos (1991)
identifies a few impasses of contemporary Human Rights' thought. I have selected
three of them which seem very relevant to me. First, contemporary Human Rights
thought, influenced by legal positivism hostile to Natural Law approaches,
largely refuses to thematize the ultimate foundations of Human Rights (1991
: 263 ff). The Human Rights' discussion refuses to acknowledge the transcendent
and remains in the realm of the immanent. It thus strongly weakens the possible
bases for Human Rights as they can only be relative :
(...) it follows, according to one of the
most elementary rules of logic which we have already mentioned, that the
fundamental conclusions cannot be 'stronger' than their founding premises
; thus, of a series of purely immanent affirmations - and which thus are
not of absolute character - one cannot draw affirmations on absolute
rights. (1991 : 268-269) -47-
Second, all attempts to justify
Human Rights merely in a procedural, contractual
or intersubjective way turn out to be sterile as they can only
provide plausible, reasonable or possible
justifications which fundamentally always only stay embedded in our
subjectivities. There is no objective criterion which could permit us to
favour and to absolutise one specific content rather than another. As he
remarks, the authors of such theories themselves consider them only as formal
theories which cannot ultimately found any specific content of Human Rights
(1991 : 265-266).
Finally, a purely material
conception of the individual is inconsistent with the acknowledging of his
dignity which could found Human Rights. He writes :
(...) the anthropological basements of
the most current attempts to found human rights, are not the most adequate
to justify them rationally ; there is an obvious contradiction between eminently
materialistic, phenomenological or empirical theories of man and the affirmation
that man has a special 'dignity', which makes him the bearer of inalienable
'rights' which he can dispose of freely. (1991 : 267-268) -48-
In
order to get out of the actual impasse of Human Rights' thought, MASSINI-CORREAS
advocates to reorient modern philosophy towards its roots as metaphysics
trying to understand the ultimate nature of things and to stop merely
deconstructing their appearance (1991 : 273).
Our approach goes in this
direction. The main difference is nevertheless that we do not think that
we will be able to find one universal Man with universal rights through
metaphysics. We rather think that metaphysics, as reflected in the different
spiritual traditions, can lead us through their dialogue to a shared picture
of Man which would at the same time stay deeply rooted in those different
traditions, and would give rise to an appropriate corresponding Human Rights'
Law, made up of local laws and their more global articulations. This is so,
as all those traditions point at the same ultimate reality, but nevertheless
from different standpoints. It is thus a homeomorphic picture of Man emerging
from interspiritual dialogue, and not a universal picture of
Man which seems to me to be able to provide a solid basis for an intercultural
understanding of dignity and for an intercultural Praxis of Human
Rights. As the spiritual traditions provide us with a picture of Man as a
being made of the two poles of personality and individuality
and whose aim it is to realise more and more completely his
individuality, they point to a universal human potential
which we can conceptualise in our Western tradition as dignity. As TAYLOR
writes (1994 : 41) :
The politics of equal dignity is based on the idea that all humans are equally worthy of respect. It is underpinned by a notion of what in human beings commands respect, however we may shy away from this metaphysical background. For Kant, whose use of the term dignity was one of the earliest influential evocations of this idea, what commanded respect in us was our status as rational agents, capable of directing our lives through principles. Something like this has been the basis for our intuitions of equal dignity ever since, though the detailed definition of it may have changed.
Thus, what is picked out as of worth here
is a universal human potential, a capacity that all humans share. This potential,
rather than anything a person may have made of it, is what ensures that each
person deserves respect.
Thus what in spiritual traditions
is conceptualized for example as the Buddha nature or the
divine nature of all beings which manifests as their potential
to enlightenment, we conceptualize it as a universal human
potential. What is interesting is, that by introducing the lived testimony
of the spiritual traditions in the notion of dignity, the latter first of
all gets anchored in a praxis. Second, it is thus linked to the attainment
of the Good, as the universal human potential is a potential
which can provide us self-knowledge through a continuous process of opening
up, leading us thus to our Human Nature, which is assumed as
being rooted in openness, wisdom, love, peace. This is important because
in the Human Rights context we could wonder why we should insure respect
for dignity, if this dignity would be rooted in the human potential to destroy
which would constitute the ultimate nature of Man. In that extent we can
somehow say that we can deem us lucky that millennary experience, through
the ever repeated realisation by men of their spiritual nature,
has shown and continues to show that ultimately Human Nature
may be good - even if this may not appear as being its most apparent
form of manifestation. This may provide us with a good reason to try to
contribute to an environment in which our human nature could freely unfold,
and which therefore necessarily must be an environment in which respect among
human beings is guaranteed. Third, to draw on living spiritual traditions
influencing the life of a lot of people may permit to open the notion of
dignity to its appropriation in cultural contexts in which our concept of
dignity does not exist as such. Ongoing dialogue between the traditions may
further this process and contribute to the emergence of a common ground for
human Human Rights' models of conduct and behaviour. It may be
able to contribute to the progressive opening up of our notion of dignity
towards a homeomorphic intercultural and Communitarian picture of Man.
Let us now try to present
one way in which, it seems to me, the notion of dignity could be opened up
to a homeomorphic intercultural understanding. In order to do so, we will
reflect upon the relation in our Western tradition between the concepts of
dignity and of authenticity. This will permit us to conceptualize in a
dialectical relationship the Western individualistic view of the Human Being
and the holistic view of the spiritual traditions, the acknowledgement of
the unity of the Human being and the acknowledgement of its diversity. In
order to do so we will base ourselves on Charles TAYLOR's article The
Politics of Recognition (1994). We will especially use the insights
he provides there on the notions of dignity and
authenticity.
For Charles TAYLOR, the evolution
of the concepts of dignity and of authenticity go hand in hand. The notion
of dignity, as we understand it today, is the result of the collapse of social
hierarchies, which used to be the basis for honour, and of their replacement
by equal citizenship. Honour in the ancient régime sense is
intrinsically linked to inequalities. For some to have honour in
this sense, it is essential that not everyone have it. (1994 :
27). On the contrary the underlying premise of dignity is that everybody
shares in it. The rise of dignity runs parallel to the
(...) new understanding of individual
identity that emerges at the end of the eighteenth century. We might speak
of an individualized identity, one that is particular to me, and that I discover
in myself. This notion arises along with an ideal, that of being true to
myself and my own particular way of being. Following Lionel Trilling's usage
in his brilliant study, I will speak of this as the ideal of
authenticity. (TAYLOR 1994 : 28)
For TAYLOR one way to describe
the development of authenticity is to see in it the development
of the eighteenth-century notion that human beings are endowed with
a moral sense, an intuitive feeling for what is right and wrong.
in which the moral accent gets displaced. By this he means that being
in touch with our feelings takes on independent and crucial moral
significance. It is no more only valued because it keeps us in
touch with our moral feelings and thus permits us to act rightly but for
itself. It becomes something we have to attain if we are to be true
and full human beings. (1994 : 28). TAYLOR develops the evolution
of the concept through the contributions of ROUSSEAU who frequently
presents the issue of morality as that of our following a voice of nature
within us (1994 : 29) and of HERDER who
(...) put forward the idea that each of us has an original way of being human : each person has his or her own measure. This idea has burrowed very deep into modern consciousness. It is a new idea. Before the late eighteenth century, no one thought that the differences between human beings had this kind of moral significance. There is a certain way of being human that is my way. I am called upon to live my life in this way, and not in imitation of anyone's else's life. But this notion gives a new importance to being true to myself. If I am not, I miss the point of my life ; I miss what being human is for me. (...)
This new ideal of authenticity was, like the
idea of dignity, also in part an offshoot of the decline of hierarchical
society. In those earlier societies, what we would now call identity was
largely fixed by one's social position. The birth of a democratic society
doesn't by itself do away with this phenomenon, because people can still
define themselves by their social roles. What does decisively undermine this
socially derived identification, however, is the ideal of authenticity itself.
As this emerges, for instance with Herder, it calls me to discover my own
original way of being. By definition, this way of being cannot be socially
derived, but must be inwardly generated. (TAYLOR 1994 : 31-32)
To
conclude TAYLOR's presentation of dignity and authenticity we should also
note that he emphasises the fundamental dialogical feature of human life
(1994 : 32 ff). He writes (TAYLOR 1994 : 34) :
Thus my discovering my own identity
doesn't mean that I work it out in isolation, but that I negotiate it through
dialogue, partly overt, partly internal, with others. That is why the development
of an ideal of inwardly generated identity gives a new importance to recognition.
My own identity crucially depends on my dialogical relations with others.
Thus, if there is a
universal human potential which can found human dignity and the
equal treatment of all human beings there is also a universal human
potential which should lead to the recognition of Man's differences
:
In the case of the politics of difference,
we might also say that a universal potential is at its basis, namely, the
potential for forming and defining one's own identity, as an individual,
and also as a culture. This potentiality must be respected equally in everyone.
But at least in the intercultural context, a stronger demand has recently
arisen : that one accord equal respect to actually evolved cultures.
(TAYLOR 1994 : 42)
What contributions can spiritual
traditions bring to the notion of authenticity correlated to the notion of
dignity as presented above ? First, spiritual traditions present themselves
as ways of discovering ourselves. They should thus be easily concilable with
the ideal of authenticity which is familiar to us. And they may permit to
enrich our understanding of authenticity as the authenticity
they propose to find is broader than the one we usually think of in Western
terms. It is not only discovering our specific, limited nature, but also
discovering our universal, unlimited nature, our
link with the whole universe. In the context of an atomised society
such as the ones in which we live (see TAYLOR 1992) this enlarging of our
perspective on authenticity may provide us with a springboard towards a more
connected view of the individual, through the discovery of what we are
deep inside ourselves. By broadening and deepening our search
of authenticity through spiritual teachings we may be able, though starting
with us, with the individual, to come to a view of ourselves embedded in
the whole of reality and linked to all of it. We may come to insights similar
to Albert EINSTEIN's (quoted in : SOGYAL RINPOCHE 1995 : 98) :
A human being is part of a whole, called
by us the Universe, a part limited in time and space. He experiences
himself, his thoughts and feelings, as something separated from the rest
- a kind of optical delusion of his consciousness. This delusion is a kind
of prison for us, restricting us to our personal desires and to affection
for a few persons nearest us. Our task must be to free ourselves from this
prison by widening our circles of compassion to embrace all living creatures
and the whole of nature in its beauty.
This nevertheless does not
entail negation of our individuality in the Western sense. We do not get
deluded in some homogeneous all encompassing reality. On the contrary, getting
a broader perspective on ourselves permits us also to understand better
our original way of being, our specificity and its role in the
broader context of reality in which it is embedded. Lama Anagarika GOVINDA
writes (1993 : 184-185, 210-211 and 231) :
In order to live, our self must submit to continuous growth and change, which one could call a continuous death and a continuous life which go on parallelly. (...) Thus the transformation embraces both change and stability, plurality and unity, movement and constancy. It has the nature of life. This is to say that it organically links the opposite poles, which constitute unsurmountable problems for logic, and unites them in a rhythm which embraces the whole. (...)
To attribute too much importance to unity is an as serious mistake as to attribute too much importance to duality or plurality. If we conceive of duality as an irreconcilable opposition between two independent principles which mutually exclude each other and not as the necessary polarity between two aspects of reality or of a superior unity - or if we only cling to one side, completely excluding or negating the other - we definitely are the victims of a serious illusion. If we try to negate the fact of polarity (by imagining that reality solely consists in unity), we only close our eyes to the most obvious reality. (...)
Just as like in an orchestra every instrument plays its own score but finds its fulfilment, its supreme realisation in the perfect coordination of all instruments and the harmonious relationship between them, each individual conscience finds its fulfilment in a perfect relationship to the universe in all its variety of forms of life and of individual forces, in a relationship which does not permit immobility or stagnation.
But only he who knows the whole of the score
can play his role to perfection. This entails that without attaining the
state of enlightenment or of universal consciousness (...), without attaining
this ultimate state we cannot find our supreme fulfilment. -49-
Knowledge of ourselves sustained
by the spiritual traditions may thus permit us to become authentic
through Self-realisation (with capital S, realisation
of our universal nature) which also entails self-realisation (with
small s, realisation of our individual nature). We have already
met this tension between universality and individuality while presenting
the notions of dharma and of svadharma in the presentation of the Indian
archetype (p 29) .
Relating authenticity to dignity
as manifestations of a universal human potential and enriching these notions
by the spiritual traditions may thus possibly enable us to think our human
unity without forgetting about its diversity, our human universality without
forgetting about its individuality. The Western concept seems thus to be
able to be enriched by a more dynamic and plural outlook on Man which views
him as a process, participating in complementarity with other processes in
the cosmic or divine processes of life. We may have
here a first step towards a Communitarian view of the self acknowledging
its unity in the complementarity of its differences. This seems absolutely
essential to me for a Communitarian conception of Human Rights. As we have
already outlined in Part II, while expliciting our choice of the paradigms
of Common Humanities and of Human Community and their
relationship, a healthy plural Human Rights thought and practice cannot grow
on unitary premises. If we want to think plurally, we seem invited to open
up the most fundamental premises of our Human Rights' thought to pluralism.
In Parts I and II we have already done so by rethinking Human Rights' Law
in an eminently plural way through the prism of a first dianthropological
praxis of Human Rights. We have called it the Social Sciences'
dianthropological praxis of Human Rights, as it still stays on the
level of logos, or rather of logoi. As we have noticed it
corresponds to the first part of RUMI's parable. We try to enrich our common
perception through the dialogue of our different points of view but still
stay on the level of logos. In this first Chapter of Part III, we
have started to propose ways permitting us to rethink the Human Rights' subject,
the Human Being in plural terms through the contribution of a second kind
of dianthropological praxis which we could call spiritual dianthropological
praxis. This spiritual dianthropological praxis is still
characterized by dialogue. But furthermore the standpoints of which the
dialoguing discourses emerge do not pertain anymore to the domain of the
mere anthropologos, but bear testimony to a reality beyond it, experienced
through spiritual experience. We have noted that the spiritual dianthropological
praxis could be seen as corresponding to the second part of RUMI's parable.
Let us now try to reconcile
these two lower-case dianthropological praxises in an
upper-case Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights. I understand
this Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights as a possible emerging
intercultural myth of Human Rights' thought and practice which could provide
us with a common horizon for intercultural Communitarian Human Rights' praxis
and with a nourishing ground for a healthy intercultural Human Rights' pluralism.
This Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights will have to emerge
in our intercultural dialogue as the frame of this dialogue, as the underlying
myth nourishing it and rendering it meaningful. It cannot be
set a priori. Therefore we will only try in the next chapter to imagine what
such a fruitful myth could consist in. And by doing so we will hopefully
take part in shaping and vivifying it.
Chapter VI : Towards a Dianthropological Praxis
of Human Rights
In this chapter we will try to imagine what a potentially fruitful grounding
myth for an intercultural praxis of Human Rights', which I will call
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights, could look like. The purpose is
to reflect upon the paradigms in which intercultural Communitarian Human
Rights' thought and practice could be embedded in order to be able to unfold.
If I have chosen to speak of myth, it is to emphasize that we try to deal
here with what could underlay, without maybe ever being very conscious, our
common intercultural Human Right's practices and discourses. We want to approach
that which could give meaning and coherence to our dialoguing Common Humanities
and to their sharing in our Human Community. As PANIKKAR writes (1979 : 344)
:
Mythos is the second dimension
of speech itself, the silence between the words, the matrix that bears the
words.
It
is this silence between the words, the matrix that could bear the
words of intercultural Human Rights' dialogue that we will try to approach
here. Of course we will not be able to grasp the mythos by our
logos. PANIKKAR reminds us that if logos pertains to the realm
of the thought, mythos belongs to the realm of the unthought. Thus
at the moment where we reveal a myth it ceases to be a myth. But PANIKKAR
also tells us, that if we cannot reveal myths, we can nevertheless contribute
to their unfolding. He writes (PANIKKAR 1979 : 345-346):
Now we cannot perceive our own myths qua myths ; we can only recognize the myths of others or those of our own past. Myths are ultimate because they do not have any other background over against which they could be recognized as such. We can only take up living myths and allow them to unfold.
(...) Although myth ceases to be myth each
time it is discovered, detached, made logos, it still remains the inexhaustible
source of renewal.
Thus, by trying to approach
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights we in fact intend to contribute,
by trying to explicit it, to its unfolding. It is our dialoguing in the frame
set by this myth, which may in fact give life to it. Thus, the proposals
I make in order to think about Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights,
should not be seen as definitive statements on what an underlying myth or
paradigm of intercultural Human Rights' thought should be. I rather intend
those proposals to be an invitation to dialogue about our common Human Rights'
praxis, to reflect upon the image we can more or less consciously have of
it, to see if we could share in the image of its founding myth
as I propose it, and to see how we could refine or enrich our perception
of this myth. It is the possible dialogue stemming from the picture I try
to give of this myth and from the reactions it may provoke that the myth
itself could be vivified and could thus become able to nourish our conscious
Human Rights' theory and practice, thus permitting us to live a Dianthropological
Praxis of Human Rights.
It
seems to me that two ternary structural principles could give an image of
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights : the first one we could see in
the outlook on Man in PANIKKAR's cosmotheandric intuition, the second is
rather linked to the ground in which Human Rights' thought and practice could
be embedded and where they could unfold. Let us start by presenting PANIKKAR's
cosmotheandric view of Man (I) before presenting the grounding of our Human
Community delimited by the cornerstones of Love, Wisdom and Peace (II). We
will then make the synthesis of both in Dianthropological Praxis of Human
Rights (II).
I. The Cosmotheandric
Intuition
In
Chapter V, we have already emphasized the importance of a Communitarian picture
of Man, in order to think about Human Rights in a Communitarian way. We have
suggested that it may be useful to try to develop homeomorphic notions which
could serve as springboards to an intercultural picture of Man, instead of
trying to think in terms of universal notions. What we have tried to do so
far, is to show how we could open up our notion of dignity to an intercultural
understanding, by opening it up to the insights of (to a large extent Asian)
spiritual traditions, thus at the same time opening up these traditions to
our understanding of dignity. For this kind of endeavour, we have seen that
it might be relevant to take into account different dimensions of Man, and
to try to articulate them. Thus, in order to broaden our concept of
dignity, we have proposed to enrich it by the acknowledgement
and the articulation of two dimensions of Man : his Human dimension and his
spiritual dimension, which we could also call his Divine dimension,
in the sense that it is a Dimension transcending the human although constituting
it, and to keep up with the terminology PANIKKAR uses to explicit his
cosmotheandric intuition.
PANIKKAR, as we will see,
takes our endeavour further. He argues that in human cultures, one not only
finds the Divine and the Human outlooks on reality,
but also a Cosmic outlook. He further argues that these three
archetypes of seeing the real (the Human, the Cosmic and the
Divine) are not contradictory or even interdependent, but should be seen
as what fundamentally makes up human reality. I think that we could understand
PANIKKAR's cosmotheandric outlook on life as an outlook acknowledging the
importance for human life of a consciousness of the individual (the Human
outlook), of his or her environment and of his or her link to it (the Cosmic
outlook) and of his or her consciousness of something that is beyond his
or her comprehension but nevertheless important for his or her life such
as reality, or human nature, or life,
or God as it provides it with some transcending unity
(the Divine outlook), and of the consciousness of the interrelation of those
three consciousnesses. PANIKKAR (1993b : 60) explains his intuition as follows
:
The cosmotheandric principle could be formulated by saying that the divine, the human and the earthly - however we may prefer to call them - are the three irreducible dimensions which constitute the real, i.e., any reality inasmuch as it is real.(...)
What this intuition emphasizes is that the
three dimensions of reality are neither three modes of a monolithic
undifferentiated reality, nor three elements of a pluralistic system. There
is rather one, though intrinsically threefold, relation which manifests the
ultimate constitution of reality. Everything that exists, any real being,
presents this triune constitution expressed in three dimensions.
PANIKKAR proposes the circle
as an appropriate way of symbolizing the cosmotheandric intuition, as there
is no circle without a center and a circumference, and that thus the three
are not the same and yet not separable. And he makes the following analogy:
The circle, only
visible from the circumference, is matter, energy, the world. And this is
so because the circumference, Man, Consciousness, encompasses it. And both
are what they are because there is God, a center, which alone - i.e., qua
God, as the ancients would put it - is a sphere whose center is everywhere
and whose circumference is
nowhere. (PANIKKAR
1993b : 75)
As
already mentioned God does not have to be understood literally.
We can also understand under God the reality providing
the link between Man and the World, the horizon into which Man
and the Cosmos are inscribed.
This outlook on the real is
all the more interesting in the search for an intercultural homeomorphical
picture of Man as it seems that envisioning all of reality in terms
of three worlds is an invariant of human culture, whether this vision is
expressed spatially, temporally, cosmologically or metaphysically.
(PANIKKAR 1993b : 56)
To
create interculturally meaningful concepts of the Human in Human
Rights' thought, PANIKKAR's cosmotheandric outlook on Man seems promising
as it could permit a mestizaje of Human Rights' concerns
through a homeomorphic picture of Man. His cosmotheandric outlook on the
real and on the human is a possible way of articulating different
archetypes of seeing the world, differently weighed by different
cultures or individuals but which nevertheless seem present in one way or
another in all of them. If either the Divine, or the
Cosmic, or the Human point of view may predominantly
characterize a specific culture, it seems very likely that in fact all cultures
to a certain extent display these different archetypes, although
weighing them differently, as we have already seen it in relation to the
legal archetypes exposed in Chapter II. We should not get blocked
on words such as Cosmic or Divine to decree that
the reality that lies behind those words has no relation to our personal
or cultural experience. We could for example note, that although for example
our Western culture is characterized, according to PANIKKAR, by a Human vision
of reality, Cosmic and Divine perspectives nevertheless
seem to play an important role in it. The importance of ecological consciousness
in our culture shows that we do not completely lack a Cosmic
outlook. And as concerns the Divine, I think we have shown in Chapter V,
that search for the Divine can also be thought of in terms of search
of what transcends us, of our human nature, of
reality, and not necessarily of God - we have also
noted that concepts as the concept of universal human potential,
although rational, are structurally near to Divine conceptions
of reality, as they have a certain ultimate character founded beyond our
understanding.
In
his article Is the notion of Human Rights a Western Concept (1984b)
PANIKKAR explains himself the relevance he sees in his cosmotheandric intuition
for an intercultural approach to Human Rights :
Room should be made for other world traditions to develop and formulate their own homeomorphic views corresponding to or opposing Western 'rights'. (...) Here the role of a cross-cultural philosophical approach is paramount. The need for human pluralism is often recognized in principle, but not often practised, not only because of the dynamism which drives the paneconomic ideology, linked with the megamachine, to expand all over the world, but also because viable alternatives are not yet theoretically worked out.
(...) An intermediary space should be found for mutual criticism that strives for mutual fecundation and enrichment. Perhaps such an interchange may help bring forth a new myth and eventually a more humane civilization. The dialogical dialogue appears as the unavoidable method.
Perhaps a suggestion here may prove helpful. Playing on the metaphor of the knots (individuality) and the net (personhood) we could probably affirm that traditional cultures have stressed the net (kinship, hierarchical structure of society, the function to be performed, the role of each part in relation to the whole), so that often the knot has been suffocated and not allowed sufficient free-space for its own self-identity. On the other hand, Modernity stresses the knots (individual free will to choose any option, the idiosyncracies of everyone, the atomization of society) so that often the knot has been lost in loneliness, alienated by its own social mobility, and wounded (or killed) in competition with other more powerful knots. Perhaps the notion of personhood as the interplay between the knots and the net, as well as the realization that freedom is not just the capacity to choose between given options but also the power to create options, could provide a starting point for the proposed mutual fecundation.
If many traditional cultures are centered
on God, and some other cultures basically cosmocentric, the culture which
has come up with the notion of Human Rights is decisively anthropocentric.
Perhaps we may now be prepared for a cosmotheandric vision of reality in
which the Divine, the Human and the Cosmic are integrated into a Whole, more
or less harmonious according to the performance of our truly human
rights. (PANIKKAR 1984a : 42-43)
After having now outlined
a picture of Man reconciling and articulating his Divine,
Cosmic and Human dimensions, differently emphasized
by different cultures, and having thus laid down possible basements for a
possibly homeomorphic, intercultural picture of Man, which could be at the
foundation of a mestizaje of Human Rights, let us now outline a possible
terrain of a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights between Love, Wisdom
and Peace.
II. Love, Wisdom and
Peace as the Cornerstones of a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights
We can represent the developments of this part as the triangle represented
above (Figure 8 ). Its summits are Love, Wisdom and Peace and its
center is the Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights which emerges through
the underlying matrix made up by the summits.
Why have I chosen Love, Wisdom and Peace as the possibly relevant cornerstones
of our Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights ? A first answer is that
they seem to be universal longings of the Human, fundamental experiences
of human life which have their structural equivalent and are thematised in
every culture. Further they seem to correspond to the underlying ideal Human
Rights seek to realise : a fraternal life (Love) of mutual understanding
(Wisdom) in Peace. But there is more to this choice. We have advocated that
in order to be sustained it could be relevant that Human Rights plunge their
roots deep into human spirituality, deep into the most profound Human experience.
And it seems that Love and Wisdom are intimately linked to the realisation
of our true nature, as we have seen it in Chapter V (p 92-93).
Let us just remind the importance of Love and Wisdom in spiritual endeavour
by a short quotation of AIVANHOV (1977 : 22 ; see also KALOU RINPOCHE 1993
: 202-204, TRUNGPA 1993 : 4 ) :
Truth is a medal of which one face is love and the other wisdom. If you seek truth independently of love and wisdom, you will not find it. But from the very moment on where you possess love and wisdom, you possess truth also, independently of the fact that you seek it or not. (1970 : 222)
-50-
A
quotation of Swâmi VIVEKANANDA, reflecting a Hindu perspective can
help us make the transition from Love and Wisdom to Peace (1972 : 114) :
What we need to do now, is to combine the
greatest heart and the highest intelligence, infinite love and infinite
knowledge. The vedantist does not give to God other attributes than these
three : He is Infinite Existence, Infinite Knowledge and Infinite Bliss,
and the vedantist considers that these three are One. Existence without knowledge
and without love cannot be ; knowledge without love and love without knowledge
cannot be. What we want, is harmony of Infinite Existence, Knowledge and
Bliss. That is what our goal is. -51-
This idea of harmony thus
can lead us to the notion of Peace. Peace can be seen as the harmony between
Infinite Existence, Knowledge and Bliss, between Infinite Truth, Wisdom and
Love which could result from enlightenment. The historical BUDDHA,
is said to have said after having attained enlightenment, but before having
started to teach (quoted in TRUNGPA 1981 : 31) :
A profound peace and without limits, that is the Teaching I have found.
We
can relate these words to our quotation of Râmana MAHARSHI on the front
page of the thesis :
Peace is always present. You only have
to move the obstacles which blur it. This peace is the Self. (1993
: 416) -53-
MAHARSHI's quotation points
us to an important aspect of Peace. Peace is not only the harmonious integration
of the whole. It is also the space in which this whole integration can take
place. In my view, Peace can fundamentally be seen as the space which permits
the deployment of life as Existence, Wisdom and Love. Or rather it can be
seen as the spacious aspect of Existence in which Existence can deploy itself.
Peace seems thus to be an essential aspect complementing Love and Wisdom.
It can be seen as the space in which Love and Wisdom can grow. We could maybe
say that it may be in Peace (the space) that we could be able to
return to Peace (the harmony).
I
think that I have given by now an insight into why Love, Wisdom and Peace
seem relevant to me as potential cornerstones of a Dianthropological Praxis
of Human Rights. I think it is very clear that these notions rather pertain
to the realm of mythos than to the realm of logos. Nevertheless,
in order to enable us to fertilize the domain of Human Rights' logos
by them, and thus also to vivify the myth of Dianthropological Praxis of
Human Rights itself, I would like to shortly present Love, Peace and Wisdom
in a way seeking to further stimulate our thought and practice of them.
In
order to do so, I will propose to present the notion of Love as Link,
Responsibility and Respect ; the notion of Wisdom as Theory, Praxis and Dialogue
; and the notion of Peace as Harmony, Freedom and Justice. All these notions
seem to me to be intimately intertwined and to lie one in each other. I will
not go into deep developments and do not intend to start an argumentation
on the reasons of my choice. I simply intend, if I could say, to plant a
seed, which I hope will grow.
Love as Link, Responsibility
and Respect
Love is the feeling, the
understanding to be linked : to be linked to others, to oneself, to
life, to one's environment, to the cosmos, to the divine. Love in its highest
expression can be summed up according to VIVEKANANDA (1972 : 45) in one insight
: I am the universe, the universe is one. This insight requires
us not to do to others what we would not want others to do to us. It requires
us to put ourselves in the place of others, and not to bring everything back
to ourselves. It makes us aware of the responsibility we bear towards
us and the others. We are linked. We cannot exist independently. People have
cared for us, helped us, loved us. We must do the same. And even if we may
think that nobody has ever done anything for us (which is hard to imagine!),
it seems nevertheless difficult to deny that we are interlinked, that we
can only live through our link with the others, and that at least to some
extent, the sufferings of the others are also our sufferings. We thus have
a responsibility to help others in their lives and to contribute to the easing
of their possible sufferings. But if love stresses unity, we should not forget
about our human condition marked by diversity. The unity of Love should not
lead us to a uniform outlook on the world. We should not impose our love
on others, as this is not true Love but selfishness. True Love starts with
the other, not with oneself. True Love thus calls for respect. Only
through respecting the other in his individuality can we really love him.
Respect is the element of prudence Love needs in order not to become excessive.
It leads us to reflect upon enlightened Love, which is Love
illuminated, guided by Wisdom.
Wisdom as Theory, Praxis
and Dialogue
Wisdom is theory, if
we understand theory as theôrein, as observation or contemplation
. It is detachment, putting into perspective. It is understanding. If Love
could be related to warmth, Wisdom can be related to light. It permits us
to see where we are going. If warmth, Love, puts things into movement, light,
Wisdom, permits to orient this movement. Wisdom is thus not theory abstracted
from reality, from action. Wisdom is theory informing action. And it is theory
stemming from action. Wisdom is thus praxis. It is linked to bearing
testimony to our existence. It therefore demands for dialogue. This
dialogue is at least double. It is dialogue with existence itself as it emerges
through praxis. It is also dialogue between the different witnesses to existence,
the others. As it makes us aware of the same reality we share, but from different
points of view, it directs us back to Love as seen above.
Peace as Harmony, Freedom
and Justice
Peace is harmony. It
presupposes the insights of Love and of Wisdom that everything is linked
and though is different. It presupposes a global perspective on the real
which understands the complementarity of its manifested differences. Building
on this understanding, Peace is the harmonious integration of reality. The
harmonious integration of reality presupposes articulation of the differences,
not destruction of these differences. It thus presupposes freedom
or space for existence. Without freedom existence could not unfold itself
harmoniously as it would be limited in its unfolding, as it would encounter
resistances. But it not only presupposes freedom and space of the whole but
also of the parts. It thus presupposes the existence of multiple spaces and
freedoms which can constitute a frame for the unfolding of existence(s).
Peace is therefore linked to justice as it presupposes that none of
these spaces invades the others. Harmonious articulation therefore necessitates
just articulation permitting the realisation of the freedom of the parts
in complementarity to the freedom of the whole. Here again justice leads
us back to freedom and harmony and further to Wisdom as theory, praxis and
dialogue and to Love as link, responsibility and respect.
We
have now approached what could constitute three mythical cornerstones of
a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights and have thus gained some insights
in the underlying matrix of a possible Dianthropological Praxis of Human
Rights. We have now given an image of the mythos which could sustain
a Communitarian Human Rights' Praxis. Let us now see how we can articulate
this mythos with the mythos of Man reflected in the cosmotheandric
intuition in the mythos of a Dianthropological Praxis of Human
Rights.
III. Towards a
Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights
To
approach Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights, we will proceed in two
steps. First we will try to link the frame provided by Love, Wisdom and Peace
with the Praxis of Human Rights it is intended to sustain. We will then add
to the picture, the actor of this praxis, the Human being in all his
cosmotheandric dimensions.
We
have said that Love, Peace and Wisdom could constitute the underlying mythical
ground on which a Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights could grow. We
will now refine the diagram we have already given. Indeed we have said that
praxis is the link of theory and practice. It is theory informed by action
and action informed by theory. Praxis is thus what gives meaning to both.
We have advocated in this thesis an approach to Human Rights based on Praxis,
by which we meant an approach as made up by the mutually depending and
interrelating of theorie(s) and of practice(s) meeting in a common Human
Rights' Praxis. We could thus, in two dimensions, represent our Human Rights
Praxis as follows (Figure 9) :
Our Human Rights' theory and practice thus meet in a shared myth of Love,
Wisdom and Peace, in our Human Rights Praxis. But what is this Praxis ? We
could say that it is life. It is that which integrates the parts, theory
and practice, and permits them to unfold as life. If we see praxis as life,
praxis is always the self and the Self. Thus the cosmotheandric intuition
could be seen as at the center of our cross above - it is there where our
praxis is. We have already represented the cosmotheandric intuition as a
circle. We can thus complement the diagram above, by a circle, whose center
is our Human Rights praxis. This will remind us that our praxis is not only
one-dimensional, but multidimensional, Human, Cosmic and Divine. To sum up
the myth of Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights, we can thus draw the
following symbol (Figure 10) which resumes it and permits its unfolding,
which in a certain way is the seed, which can grow and unfold if it is taken
care of, if it gets light (wisdom), water (love) and space (peace) :
We have gone a long way since the beginning of this thesis. We have followed
the path of healthy pluralism, which in fact was already mapped
out by the three quotations on the front page. We have started by playing
the role of living rosettas in order to be able to approach our
Common Humanities characterized by unity in diversity, by trying to immerse
ourselves in the different cultures and to approach them from within. We
have thus laid down the first foundations for a dialogical pattern of interaction
for cultures, for the elaboration of a platform of mutual enrichment in
intercultural dialogue on the Human Rights' ideal. This pattern permitted
us to avoid uniformising universalism or absolute relativism. It laid down
the bases permitting us to think unity as a complementarity of differences,
and not as necessarily uniformization of all differences.
This led us to reflect upon our Human Community or Human Rights' Community.
We advocated that it is in the Human Community that our Common Humanities
could be able to meet in their shared praxis.
We could conceive of our life as made up of parallels. In our specific context
of an intercultural reflection on Human Rights, theory and practice or our
different ways to be Human could be approached as parallels. Parallels cannot
exist alone. They can only exist in relation to one another. On similar lines,
we could think of theory and of practice or of humans as parallels : theory
cannot exist without practice ; and a human being cannot exist alone - but
only parallelly to others. Thus thinking in terms of parallels
may permit us to get aware of the dialectical relations between things -
of the necessarily at least dual structure of reality. But it may be possible
to see more in the image of parallels. Could we not also see them as opening
the way to a dialogical and not merely dialectical approach to reality ?
Parallels can be seen not only as representing a dialectical relationship
through their parallelism. They could also be seen as an invitation to a
dialogical approach to life if we try to reflect upon their possible meeting.
Where could such a logic defying meeting of parallels take place ? Well,
maybe as the mathematical axiom of their meeting in infinity, which may have
provided the inspiration to Christian MORGENSTERN's poem on the two parallels
quoted on the front page, suggests : in the infinite. Parallels could maybe
meet in the infinite and become a circle whose center is everywhere
and whose circumference is nowhere. By being seen as possibly meeting
in the circle, in the infinite, the image of parallels may give us a hint
on how to think contradictions together, without necessarily
having to limit ourselves to dialectics. We have to change the frame of reference
: in the finite parallels can never meet - if they can they only can in the
infinite. In a similar way it may be difficult to make parallels,
for instance universalism and relativism, meet in the Human Rights' discussion
on a purely rational, theoretical level - which necessarily constitutes a
limited frame. So it seems that in order to break out of unsolvable paradoxes,
we might be invited to open up our frame of reflection to the
infinite, to life and therefore to practice and Praxis. That is what I have
tried to show in Part II : a truly dialogical approach to Human Rights in
the intercultural context cannot remain in the pure domain of dialectics
- it must open itself up to praxis : merely thinking in terms of Human
Rights' System or even of dialectical game will not suffice.
A dialogical approach to Human Rights seems to me only possible within a
paradigm of a Human Community which could maybe be approached through a Jeu
de l'oie methodology.
Common Humanities and Human Community permitted us to engage in a social
sciences' dianthropological praxis of Human Rights characterized through
a praxis of Human Rights informed by the different anthropologies of Men
and by their mutual dialogue and interfecundation. In Part III we have sought
to complement this dianthropological praxis of Human Rights by a spiritual
dianthropological praxis of Human Rights. The idea was to enrich our
view on Human Rights by a dialogue founded in bases beyond the pure realm
of logos, in deep inner spiritual experience. We have tried to see how spiritual
experience could enrich our Human Rights' thought. We have then tried to
propose a picture of what a fruitful myth which could sustain pluralistic
and dialogical praxis of Human Rights could look like. We have called this
myth we tried to approach Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights. And we
have described it as a myth structured through a
cosmotheandric outlook on Man and through a fertile ground for
the growing of intercultural Human Rights characterized by Love, Wisdom and
Peace
We have noted in our introduction that Common Humanities, Human Community
and Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights constitute three paradigms for
intercultural Human Rights praxis which could lead to an intercultural
mestizaje of Human Rights. We should maybe specify that Dianthropological
Praxis of Human Rights as a myth certainly has a paradigmatic aspect, but
as we have seen, it in fact goes far beyond what one would call a simple
paradigm which pertains more to the domain of logos and of methods or techniques
(poiesis) than to the domains of myth and praxis. Though keeping
this in mind, let us nevertheless keep on talking here of paradigms
for the sake of simplicity. We have advocated that the three proposed paradigms
are not independent one of another, even if they can be thought of and criticized
independently. They seem to me intimately interrelated and eminently
complementary. They are the organic parts of a whole whose founding myth
and horizon is Dianthropological Praxis of Human Rights, whose basements
in the real world is our Common Humanities and whose place of
concretisation is the Human Community. There can be no Human Rights' Praxis
without a base, a place for its unfolding, and a horizon for its unfolding.
We see how much our whole outlook is permeated by a triune view of reality,
already presented above by PANIKKAR.
We have now arrived at our conclusion. But our conclusion is rather the planting
of a seed. It is thus just the very beginning of a new process of unfolding.
I hope that the readers will take up the invitation to the caring for that
seed. I hope that they will help it to grow through their contribution of
Love, Wisdom and Peace, permitting thus its wonderful unfolding. Omraam
Mikhaël AIVANHOV encourages his disciples to work on themselves, and
we can also see it as an encouragement to work on our Dianthropological Praxis
of Human Rights (1997 : 270-271) :
You can start building your future from this very moment on. Through desire, thought, prayer, imagination, you can choose the best orientation, to manifest yourselves one day as beings of peace, of goodness, of light. But above all, once you have chosen this orientation, cling to it. Learn to channel all your energies and to orient them towards this world of harmony and of love. Even if some shadows appear from time to time, this will not last : if you always keep the right interior orientation, a day will come where you will not be deflected anymore. That is the essential, and I only deal with the essential. (...)
Whatever may happen, continue to build your future, do not get discouraged
: your sufferings, your ordeals will soon seem to you like the waves of a
tempest over which you would be floating. If you happen to feel weighed down
by your ordeals, it is because you did not manage to keep a view on your
luminous future. Your horizon is obstructed, but it is obstructed because
you have obstructed it, and it is up to you to open up a window to see the
sun. -54-
So let us build our future, but not only our individual future, but the future
of our whole Human Community. Let us let the sun shine in. But especially
in our intercultural context, let us not forget that the Sun of Humanity
shines through all the bright colours of the rainbow. Let us thus build a
common future, as bright but also as coloured as the Rainbow. Let us follow
the invitation of Tierno BOKAR, a sufi master born in the second half of
the last century in the present Mali, and who died in the first half of this
century. We can again extend his invitation from its solely religious context
to the broader context of the endeavour towards a peaceful and shared living
together characterized by its enrichment through our diversities of beliefs,
world views and traditions but nevertheless sharing in a common horizon which
we can call whatever we want : Humanity, God, the
Cosmos or still something else, according to our own personal
perspectives. Tierno BOKAR said (in BA 1994 : 145-146) :
The rainbow owes its beauty to the varied tones of its colours. Similarly, we consider the voices of the diverse believers which raise from all points of the world like a symphony in praise of God who can only be Unique.
We bitterly deplore the lack of understanding of certain religious people
(...) which leads them to reject as dissonant the anthem of their neighbour.
To fight against this tendency, my brothers in God, whatever religion or
congregation you may be affiliated to, meditate longly on this verse :
MORGENSTERN (1973 : 298-299) :
The two parallels
Once went to parallels
out in the infinite,
two straight souls
and from a solid home.
They did not want to intersect
until their peaceful grave
this was, what to say,
both's secret pride and way.
But after ten lightyears
of such common travelling
the lonesome couple felt
not really earthly anymore.
Were they still parallels ?
They couldn't say, -
they were only like two souls flowing
together through eternal Light.
The eternal Light permeated them
thus they became one in Him :
eternity swallowed them
just like two seraphim.
MAHARSHI (1993 : 416) :
Peace is always present.
You only have to move the obstacles
which blur it.
This peace is the Self.
-1- (p 4-5) :
Penser le droit, c'est d'abord se méfier de ce qu'en disent les spécialistes. CLAUZEWITH, le fondateur de la stratégie moderne, disait que la guerre était trop importante pour la confier aux seuls militaires. Quelques-uns d'entre nous, anthropologues, disons : 'le droit est trop important pour être confié aux seuls juristes'.
Le droit, ce n'est pas ce qu'en disent les juristes, c'est ce qu'en font
les acteurs. C'est ce qu'en font les citoyens. Ce sont les pratiques des
citoyens qui nous permettent de mesurer l'efficacité du droit. Le
droit n'est pas dans les textes, il est dans les pratiques. (LE ROY
1994a : 29)
INTRODUCTION
-2- (p 11) :
On jouait à toutes les tables, et souvent gros. La nuit avait été longue et la fumée qui depuis longtemps avait envahi le tripot empêchait de voir de l'une à l'autre. Il eût fallu se déplacer et l'on aurait alors été émerveillé par la variété. Chaque table jouait un jeu différent : ici les tarots, le lasquenet, le pamphile, le polignac et le mistigri, là le whist, le bridge et le boston, plus loin la belote, la bataille et même le bonneteau. Tout à coup les joueurs de belote quittèrent leur table pour observer celle de bridge. L'un d'eux revint assez vite ayant remarqué que les bridgeurs ne connaissaient pas les règles du jeu (il songeait à celles de la belote) et commettaient beaucoup d'erreurs : optimiste et bienveillant, il pensa qu'ils finiraient par les apprendre et par savoir jouer. Les ayant observés plus longtemps, un de ses camarades comprit qu'ils ne s'essayaient pas à la belote mais à un autre jeu : il nota la façon dont ils classaient les cartes et les abattaient et rejoignit le premier pour lui faire part de sa découverte. C'est alors que le troisième joueur de belote, ayant deviné qu'il fallait connaître les règles du bridge pour comprendre la partie s'en enquit auprès des joueurs : ils lui remirent un manuel, ajoutant qu'il ne suffirait pas de bien lire et qu'il lui faudrait une longue pratique du tripot pour prétendre connaître le bridge.
Ainsi vont le sociétés humaines. Chacune joue un jeu particulier
que les autres peinent à déchiffrer. (ALLIOT 1984 :
269)
CHAPTER I
-3- (p 13-14) :
A partir du moment où on se refuse à la sécurité
du particularisme disciplinaire et au rêve d'une totalisation du discours,
on renonce aux assurances du savoir établi (parcellaire ou total,
peu importe), pour ordonner la production du savoir à un incessant
travail d'écart entre les discours existants. C'est dans le creux
de cet entre-deux que se dévoile la figure de notre
épistème, comme c'est dans l'échange du dialogue que
s'articule le sens de notre praxis. (van de KERCHOVE, OST 1992: 52)
-4- (p 14) :
Le relativiste ne porte pas de jugement sur les autres. L'universaliste
conscient peut les condamner; mais il le fait au nom d'une morale ouvertement
assumée, qui du coup peut être mise en question. L'universaliste
inconscient est inattaquable, puisqu'il prétend être relativiste;
mais cela ne l'empêche pas de porter des jugements sur les autres et
de leur imposer son idéal. Il a l'agressivité du second et
la bonne conscience du premier : il est assimilateur en toute innocence,
parce qu'il ne s'est pas aperçu de la différence des autres.
(TODOROV 1992b : 71)
-5- (p 15-16) :
Dieu crée d'abord Adam, soit l'homme indifférencié,
prototype de l'espèce humaine. Puis dans un deuxième temps,
il extrait en quelque sorte de cet être indifférencié
un être de sexe différent. Voici Adam face à Eve, cette
fois en tant que mâle et femelle de l'espèce humaine. Dans cette
curieuse opération, Adam a en somme changé d'identité
tandis qu'apparaissent un être qui est à la fois membre de
l'espèce humaine et différent du représentant majeur
de cette espèce. Adam, ou dans notre langue l'homme, est deux choses
à la fois: le représentant de l'espèce humaine et le
prototype mâle de cette espèce. A un premier niveau homme et
femme sont identiques, à un second niveau la femme est l'opposé
ou le contraire de l'homme. Ces deux relations prises ensembles
caractérisent la relation hiérarchique , qui ne peut être
mieux symbolisée que par l'englobement matériel de la future
Eve dans le corps du premier Adam. Cette relation hiérarchique est
très généralement celle entre un tout (ou un ensemble)
et un élément de ce tout (ou ensemble): l'élément
fait partie de l'ensemble, lui est en ce sens consubstantiel ou identique,
et en même temps il s'en distingue ou s'oppose à lui. Il n'y
a pas d'autre façon de l'exprimer en termes logiques que de juxtaposer
à deux niveaux différents ces deux propositions qui prises
ensembles se contredisent. C'est ce que je désigne comme
englobement du contraire. (DUMONT 1991: 140-141, dans une version
un peu différente : DUMONT 1979 : 397)
-6- (p 18) :
Le bon universalisme est donc d'abord celui qui ne déduit
pas l'identité humaine d'un principe, quel qu'il soit, mais qui part
d'une connaissance approfondie du particulier, eût qui avance par
tâtonnements (...). Il est de plus celui qui repose sur au moins deux
particuliers (...) et donc sur l'établissement d'un dialogue entre
eux; Rousseau détruit ici la fausse évidence dont part
l'éthnocentriste, la déduction de l'universel à partir
d'un particulier. L'universel est l'horizon d'entente entre deux particuliers;
on ne l'atteindra peut-être jamais, mais on a néanmoins besoin
de le postuler pour rendre intelligibles les particuliers existants.
(TODOROV 1992b : 34)
-7- (p 20) :
(...) ce qu'il faut bien comprendre, c'est que ce nous
dialogual ne se construit pas de la sommation brute de deux entités
monolithiques: un je et untu constitués tels
qu'en eux-mêmes... Ce je et ce tu entre lesquels
circule la parole sont, dès l'abord, divisés, scindés
par la fracture où l'autre se fait entendre. Il n'y a de dialogue
possible que parce que s'est déjà creusée au sein du
je la place où s'inscrira la voix de l'interlocuteur.
(van de KERCHOVE, OST 1992 : 64)
-8- (p 21) :
L'ethnologue qui a tellement bien assimilé la vue du monde des
Bororos qu'il ne peut plus le voir qu'à leur façon, n'est plus
un ethnologue, c'est un Bororo - et les Bororos ne sont pas des ethnologues.
Sa raison d'être n'est pas de s'assimiler aux Bororos, mais d'expliquer
aux Parisiens, aux Londoniens, aux New Yorkais de 1965 cette autre humanité
que représentent les Bororos. Et cela, il ne peut le faire que dans
le langage, au sens plus profond du terme, dans le système
catégorial des Parisiens, Londoniens, etc. Or, ces langages ne sont
pas des codes équivalents - précisément
parce que dans leur structuration, les significations imaginaires jouent
un rôle central. (CASTORIADIS 1992 : 228)
-9- (p 21) :
(...) ne sont pas seulement de l'ordre du logos mais de l'ordre du
mythos c'est-à-dire de l'ordre des différences ultimes. Or
les différences ultimes ne sont pas dialectiques (ce qui ne veut pas
dire qu'elles sont non-dialectiques ou anti-dialectiques). (VACHON
1990 : 169)
-10- (p 22) :
Standpunkte und Perspektiven rücken notwendig ins Zentrum der
Aufmerksamkeit, sobald das Konzept des universellen Beobachters verabschiedet
oder seine Gültigkeit eingegrenzt ist. Mit dem Verständnis der
Bedeutung der Wahl des Bezugs- oder Beobachtungspunktes zeigt sich auch die
Hohlheit des Relativismusgezeters in der Pluralitätsdiskussion. Wie
Mandelbrot (...) zeigt, hängt selbst im physikalischen Mesobereich,
dem Inbegriff von Objektivität und Stabilität, der Messwert vom
Beobachtungsstandpunkt ab (...) Die Wahl des Massstabes (des Standpunkts)
wird zur Frage der Angemessenheit im Zusammenhang der jeweiligen Ziele und
Interessen. Ist der Beobachtungspunkt aber gewählt und definiert, dann
ist das ermitteln (...) eine Frage der Messgenauigkeit, wie eh und je. Dasselbe
gilt für die Argumentation von Übergängen zwischen
inkommensurablen Paradigmen. Solche können nur im konkreten Zusammenhang
argumentiert werden, daher ist sowohl die Angemessenheit des gewählten
Standpunkts (Meta-Diskurses) als auch die Korrektheit der - aus der
gewählten Perspektive - durchgeführten Beobachtung zu belegen.
(BAUER 1996: 199-200)
CHAPTER II
-11- (p 23) :
Sa généralité vient de ce qu'il est dans la nature de l'homme et de la société. Etre, c'est lutter, individuellement ou collectivement. Mais nul ne peut lutter sur une marche de son domaine que s'il est assuré de la paix sur toutes ses autres frontières. Et la lutte de ses membres n'est pas sans danger pour le groupe. Dans les domaines qu'une société considère comme vitaux - et là-dessus chacune a sa propre conception - son existence n'est possible que si ses membres contrôlent, quand ils le peuvent, ces luttes ou du moins les pratiques qui en résultent. Vivre en société, ce n'est donc pas seulement lutter, c'est aussi s'entendre sur la légitimité ou l'illégitimité de ces pratiques et sur la suite qu'il convient de leur donner. La socialité exige le consensus. Le phénomène est général parce qu'il tient à la nature de l'individu (la lutte) et aux exigences de la vie en société (le consensus). (...)
Le droit d'une société s'ordonne ainsi autour des limites des sphères d'action de chacun dans les domaines qu'elle tient pour vitaux : il est à la fois consensus sur ces limites et pratiques visant ou aboutissant à les confirmer ou à les déplacer.
Ainsi défini le droit n'est lié par nature ni à l'existence
d'un Etat, ni à la formulation de règles, ni à la
reconnaissance de sa rationalité. (ALLIOT 1983b : 209-210)
-12- (p 23) :
Qui veut comprendre la forme et le sens des institutions juridiques
d'une société a donc intérêt à les rapporter
non aux institutions de sa propre société - le rapprochement
serait superficiel - mais à l'univers de celle dans laquelle il les
observe. (ALLIOT 1983b : 215)
-13- (p 25) :
Le modèle constitue une représentation du
phénomène à la fois simplifiée et globale. En
effet on ne fait pas un modèle pour présenter toutes les
propriétés d'un phénomène, toutes les relations
que les êtres ont entre eux, tous les aspects du fait concret. Au
contraire, on envisage le phénomène d'un certain point de vue
(...) On abstrait certains aspects du concret, ce qui simplifie. Par ailleurs
les aspects retenus ne sont pas arbitraires; ils sont choisis d'un certain
point de vue, mais tous ceux qui importent à ce point de vue doivent
être choisis, ce qui rend globale la représentation fournie
par le modèle. (RÉGNIER 1971 : 18-19)
-14- (p 27) :
Un quelque chose était, non défini mais accompli
Né avant Ciel-et-Terre
Sans parole comme sans borne
Indépendant inaltérable
Se jouant partout sans fatigue
En somme la Mère du monde
Ne sachant pas son nom je la dénomme Voie
(...)
(...) l'Homme est l'un des quatre Grands du monde
L'Homme suit les voies de la Terre
La Terre suit les voies du Ciel
Le Ciel suit les voies de la Voie
Et la Voie suit ses propres voies. (LAO-TZEU 1979 : 69)
-15- (p 27) :
Gouvernez à force de lois, maintenez l'ordre à coups
de châtiments, le peuple se contentera d'optempérer, sans
éprouver la moindre honte. Gouvernez par la Vertu, harmonisez par
les rites, le peuple non seulement connaîtra la honte, mais de
lui-même tendra vers le Bien. (CONFUCIUS (1981 : 33)
-16- (p 30) :
A l'image de ce Dieu, fonction absolue au-delà de l'être, l'univers n'est pas un ensemble d'êtres mais un ensemble de fonctions qui déterminent des êtres.
C'est le cas des fonctions familiales et sociales qui déterminent le statut des individus. En Europe l'individu est une personne de la naissance à la mort, avec un droit aux droits invariables pour chacun et identique pour tous. La notion de personne juridique n'appartient pas aux Droits originellement africains. On y trouve celle de statut et de statut déterminé par les fonctions exercées : le statut individuel est d'autant plus important qu'on avance en âge, qu'on est marié (et, pour un homme, polygame), qu'on a des enfants, qu'on est à la tête d'un lignage, etc. (...)
L'être est si peu stable qu'on passe facilement d'une forme d'être
à une autre. (ALLIOT 1984 : 274-275)
-17- (p 30-31) :
La coutume n'est pas un être, comme serait un corpus de lois
: elle est la manière d'être, de parler, d'agir qui permet à
chacun de contribuer au mieux au maintien de la cohésion du groupe.
(...) De plus cette même fonction de cohésion fait qu'on évite
souvent d'invoquer la coutume : on fait en sorte que les conflits n'aillent
pas jusqu'à un affrontement ouvert. Et lorsqu'on ne peut faire autrement,
on avance sur la voie de la solution, moins par référence à
des règles antérieurement arrêtées que, cas par
cas, conformément à ce qu'on estime l'intérêt
du groupe. A l'application de la loi, on préfère la solution
qui se dégage dans le ventre du village. (ALLIOT
1984 : 277)
-18- (p 31) :
Nous somme aux antipodes du système dans lequel, à l'image
d'un Dieu dont tout dépend dans une création continue de chaque
instant, les droits des uns et des autres ne leur sont maintenus que par
la grâce de celui qui est l'auteur de tous les droits, l'Etat. Le droit
des communautés n'a pas besoin d'un pouvoir qui veuille le maintenir.
Il est la conséquence nécessaire de leur structure. (ALLIOT
1980a : 158)
-19- (p 31-32) :
(...) pour l'occident chrétien Dieu est Celui qui est
avant d'être celui qui crée : il Est de toute éternité,
il aurait pu ne pas créer, ou créer autrement. En lui l'Etre
prime l'action. A son image, les occidentaux affirmeront le primat de
l'être sur la fonction. (...) De même il n'est pas indifférent
de savoir que pour l'occident chrétien le Dieu unique est radicalement
extérieur à sa création, qu'il la recrée à
chaque instant et qu'il la gouverne souverainement par la contrainte uniforme
de ses lois et décrets. (ALLIOT 1984 : 271)
-20- (p 32) :
La société est alors décentrée : elle projette
son centre en dehors d'elle même; au dessus d'elle même. Les
rapports entre ces membres changent totalement. Il ne s'agit plus de rechercher
à chaque instant entre soi l'attitude juste. L'attitude juste, c'est
de se conformer au système de règles établi par le pouvoir
ou, si elles ne sont pas satisfaisantes, de réclamer une nouvelle
loi, une nouvelle réglementation. (ALLIOT 1983b : 234)
-21- (p 36) :
L'homme religieux verra en dharma la loi de Dieu; l'homme moral le
verra comme le principe intérieur qui fournit un critérium
du bien et du mal; le juriste le verra comme loi (...); le psychologue soulignera
la tradition, la coutume, l'esprit social; le philosophe y verra la conscience
de l'espèce ou la conscience de l'unité, qui par sa nature
même poussera finalement l'homme à manifester la bonté
ou le sens de l'unité; l'idéaliste y verra l'idéal;
le réaliste, la loi qui est derrière le spectacle apparent
de la vie; le mystique pratique y verra la force (...) qui amène
l'harmonie dans l'unité. Mais en vérité le dharma
est le principe à la base de ces manifestations, contenu en elles
toutes, et sous-jacent à toutes ces conceptions. (MEES cité
dans : Herbert, 1988: 117-118)
INTRODUCTION
-22- (p 47) :
Le Mulla, qui venait d'être nommé magistrat, jugeait sa première affaire. Le plaignant exposa son problème de façon si convaincante que Nasrudin s'exclama:
Je crois que tu as raison!
Le greffier le pria de se contenir car le prévenu n'avait pas encore été entendu.
Nasrudin fut si transporté par l'éloquence du prévenu qu'il s'écria, dès que celui-ci eut fini de parler:
Je crois que tu as raison!
Le greffier n'en put supporter davantage:
Votre Honneur, ils ne peuvent avoir raison tous les deux.
- Je crois que tu as raison! dit Nasrudin. (SHAH 1989: 67)
CHAPTER III
-23- (p 48-49) :
Nous avons vite appris que les rêves de l'époque moderne
n'étaient que des illusions. Le temps a dévoilé les
imperfections du droit moderne; il a montré combien
l'universalisme était un leurre, et que le règne suprême
de la loi ne réglait pas tout. L'observation de la réalité
juridique quotidienne a amené de nombreux juristes qui s'intéressent
au problème des fondements du droit, à reconnaître que
tout droit est relatif, qu'il existe un pluralisme des sources du droit,
et qu'un retour au pragmatisme s'impose. (ARNAUD 1990: 81)
-24- (p 49) :
La pensée moderniste affirme que les êtres humains
appartiennent à un monde gouverné par des lois naturelles que
la raison découvre et auxquelles elle est elle-même soumise.
Et elle identifie le peuple, la nation, l'ensemble des hommes à un
corps social qui fonctionne lui aussi selon des lois naturelles et qui doit
se débarrasser des formes d'organisation et de domination irrationnelles
qui cherchent frauduleusement à se faire légitimer par le recours
à une révélation ou à une décision
supra-humaine. (TOURAINE 1992 : 51)
-25- (p 50) :
(d)'une simple mascarade au masque, d'un personnage à
une personne, à un nom, à un individu, de celui-ci à
un être d'une valeur métaphysique et morale, d'une conscience
morale à un être sacré, de celui-ci à une forme
fondamentale de la pensée et de l'action (...) And he adds :
Qui sait même si cette catégorie que tous
ici nous croyons fondée sera toujours reconnue comme telle ? Elle
n'est formée que pour nous, chez nous. (MAUSS 1995 : 362)
-26- (p 50-51) :
La loi qui dans son aspect le plus fondamental était une expression de l'ordre découvert dans la nature par l'esprit humain, devient dans sa totalité expression du pouvoir ou de la volonté du législateur. De plus, tandis que que le droit était conçu comme une relation juste entre êtres sociaux, il devient la reconnaissance sociale du pouvoir (potestas) de l'individu. Occam est ainsi le fondateur de la théorie subjective du droit, qui est en fait la théorie moderne du droit. (...)
Pour les modernes (...) le Droit naturel (...) ne traite pas d'êtres sociaux mais d'individus, c'est-à-dire d'hommes dont chacun se suffit à lui-même en tant que fait à l'image de Dieu et en tant que dépositaire de la raison. Il en résulte que (...) les principes fondamentaux de la constitution de l'Etat (et de la société) sont à extraire ou à déduire, des propriétés et qualités inhérentes à l'homme considéré comme un être autonome, indépendamment de toute attache sociale ou politique. L'état de nature est l'état (...) où l'on considère seulement l'homme individuel, (...) où les hommes sont supposés avoir vécu avant la fondation de la société et de l'Etat. Déduire de cet état de nature logique ou hypothétique les principes de la vie sociale et politique peut bien apparaître une tâche paradoxale et ingrate. C'est pourtant ce qu'ont entrepris les théoriciens du Droit naturel moderne, et c'est en le faisant qu'ils ont jeté les bases de l'Etat démocratique moderne.
(DUMONT 1991 : 87 and 97)
-27- (p 53) :
(...) le multijuridisme qui intègre le multiple dans l'idée
juridique doit être abordé non comme un ensemble statique
d'injonctions ou de sanctions mais comme un système ouvert, dynamique,
comme un jeu ou comme un processus dont on doit reformuler les règles
par un nouveau paradigme. (LE ROY 1996a : 8)
-28- (p 55-56) :
En privilégiant la négociation et en orientant le justiciable vers la recherche d'un consensus qui ne se soucie pas de dire le droit mais de concilier des points de vue et les intérêts, les sociétés inventent un nouveau type de droit qui n'a pas besoin de s'exprimer dans la forme canonique du code juridique et d'être énoncé par une instance législative.
Cette expérience que nous désignons sous l'expression droit de la pratique, au double sens qu'il dépend des applications qui en sont faites et des clients qui y adhèrent, ne recourt que très accessoirement aux précédents. Plutôt que de travailler en temps reconstitué comme dans le procès pénal, ou en temps réel (pour les juges des mineurs, (...)) le médiateur africain investit dans le futur et dans le long terme des rapports sociaux à venir.
En outre, il s'inscrit dans un contexte sociétaire nouveau et fort intéressant : de nouvelles cultures communes. (...) Tout en s'opposant aux cultures officielles, à la française dans les cas observés en Afrique de l'Ouest, ces nouvelles manifestations culturelles ne se présentent pas comme tournées vers le passé et privilégiant les fondements de l'éthnicité, sauf (...) chez certains fondamentalistes musulmans de Kaolak à Kano. (...)
C'est bien une véritable culture qui émerge et que l'on dit commune non point parce qu'elle serait seulement populaire mais surtout parce qu'elle partage des traits communs avec les cultures antérieures. Enracinées dans les valeurs du terroir comme les cultures natives dont elle est issue, sensible à un islam tolérant et ouvert au monde, se voulant immédiatement efficace et soucieuse de performances, au moins politiques, comme dans les sociétés modernes, cette culture wolophone est à la fois une synthèse, et donc un métissage de cultures antérieures et la manifestation d'une postmodernité. Culture de l'action, de la débrouillardise (...), de la gestion tensionnelle des contradictions, la wolofisation (...) exprime les modalités de vie en société sans se soucier de sacrifier au culte de la modernité. Ce ne sont pas les institutions qui sont invoquées mais leurs bénéficiaires. (...)
Au fur et à mesure que la réflexion s'est développée, on a pu s'apercevoir que ce n'est pas en termes de justice ou de justiciable que la recherche d'une certaine pacification des rapports sociaux s'exprime. De moins en moins sensibles à nos fictions et à nos mythes juridiques, les sociétés africaines disent crûment que la justice d'Etat n'est qu'une arène de négociation parmi d'autres, souvent moins efficace que la gestion en face à face du conflit. Pour elles, le droit est mise en forme des conflits, émergence des consensus et gestion sur le long terme des solutions dès lors qu'elles assurent la reproduction des principales articulations de la vie sociale.
Toutes ces explications sont à la fois familières ou banales pour l'Africain et l'africaniste et étonnantes pour le spectateur étranger (...) les représentations institutionnelles qui, du XVIe au XVIIIe siècles ont fondé la modernité sont maintenant dépassées. Sans le savoir nous sommes déjà en post-modernité (...)
A défaut de justiciable on a donc découvert l'émergence
d'une nouvelle aspiration à la justice sociale et à la
réconciliation de l'Afrique avec son histoire. (LE ROY 1990b
: 118-120)
-29- (p 56) :
(...) dans une société différenciée, chaque
personne doit affronter quotidiennement des situations relevant de mondes
distincts, savoir les reconnaître et se montrer capable de s'y ajuster.
On peut qualifier ces sociétés de complexes au
sens où leurs membres doivent posséder la compétence
nécessaire pour identifier la nature de la situation et traverser
des situations relevant de mondes différents (...) Bien que le jeu
soit étroitement limité par le dispositif de la situation,
un modèle à plusieurs mondes donne aux acteurs la possibilité
de se soustraire à une épreuve et, prenant appui sur un principe
extérieur, d'en contester la validité ou même de retourner
la situation en engageant une épreuve valide dans un monde
différent. Il inclut par là la possibilité de la critique
dont les constructions déterministes ne parviennent pas à rendre
compte. (BOLTANSKI, THEVENOT 1991 : 266-267)
-30- (p 59-60) :
C'est dans la perspective d'un modèle interculturel qu'il conviendra de renouveler, d'un point de vue philosophique, politique et pratique, le principe de la complémentarité des différences.
Déjà reconnu dans les traditions animistes et indiennes, peu éloigné des traditions confucéenne et musulmane, ce principe de complémentarité des différences pose dans la tradition occidentale des difficultés que la recherche devra ultérieurement identifier et contribuer à résoudre. (...)
Dans l'état actuel de la recherche anthropologique, et compte tenu
de l'inscription de l'anthropologie dans une conception occidentale de la
science, donc dans sa vision du monde, la priorité doit être
accordée à un enrichissement de sa conception
sous-jacente aux droits de l'homme, en revalorisant l'idée (noumen
?) de respect de l'autre et en réintroduisant le principe de la
complémentarité des différences. Sans mésestimer
les difficultés qui apparaissent devant nous, nous devons être
convaincu que face aux turbulences qui s'annoncent, seule une exigence
éthique et épistémique est susceptible de fonder un
futur commun et une société pacifiée. (LE ROY
1997a : 15)
-31- (p 62) :
Au fonds il s'agit de donner aux droits de l'homme même un
caractère dialogal et plural. Pour que les droits de l'homme puissent
être universels il ne suffit pas qu'ils émergent d'un dialogue
interculturel s'ils sont ensuite figés dans une forme, absolue et
éternelle, judéo-chrétienne, d'ordre imposé
uniformément à tous. Il faut sauvegarder dans leur forme même
leur caractère dialogal et plural. La question qui se pose est alors
de savoir ce qui fera l'unité, l'universalité de ces droits.
Je pense qu'il faut concevoir les droits de l'homme comme une plaque tournante,
comme un échangeur entre les différentes logiques sociétales,
comme, pour reprendre l'image de Raimundo Panikkar à propos de la
personne (...), un noeud formant partie intrinsèque du
réseau des relations et des problématiques qui constituent
le réel des droits de l'homme. Ce rôle de plaque tournante peut
être joué par une déclaration à caractère
homéomorphe qui énoncerait les objectifs à atteindre
par toute l'humanité tout en renvoyant chaque culture à ses
propres représentations pour y trouver les fondements et les moyens
d'atteindre ces objectifs. Il s'agira donc de construire les droits de l'homme
sous la forme d'un système dynamique ouvert, structuré par
des noeuds, les concepts homéomorphes. L'universalité ne
résidera donc pas dans l'être abstrait du concept né
de la rationalité qui devra s'imposer à tous, mais dans le
fait que ce concept renverra aux objectifs universels, formulés sous
forme de concepts homéomorphes, comme ils sont conçus,
appréhendés et concrétisés par et dans les
différentes cultures, desquelles les concepts homéomorphes
ont d'ailleurs eux même émergés dans le dialogue
interculturel. (EBERHARD 1996 : 51)
CHAPTER IV
-32- (p 66) :
(...) il apparaît qu'avec le modèle du jeu s'annonce une méthode dialectique. Cette théorie dialectique entend fournir une représentation cohérente tant du phénomène juridique lui-même que de l'épistémologie de sa science et de l'éthique de sa mise en oeuvre. Sur chacun de ces plans, la pluralité est substituée à l'unité, la récursivité prend la place de la linéarité, la gradualité est préférée à la binarité, tandis que l'incertitude (qui ne signifie pas pourtant l'aléa complet), adaptée à la complexité des temps présents, est assumée en lieu et place de la pseudo-sécurité que croient garantir les pensées de la simplicité. (OST, van de KERCHOVE 1993a : 191)
-33- (p 67) :
Isoler des objets (...) de leur environnement et de l'observateur qui
les étudie (...), établir des relations linéaires et
hiérarchisées entre ces éléments : tel est le
propre de la rationalité, du paradigme cartésien.
Philosophie du tiers exclu, qui s'ancre solidement sur les principes
d'identité (A=A) et de non-contradiction (A n'est pas non-A). Le
modèle dialectique de la complexité est, au contraire, celui
du tiers inclus. Ce modèle suppose que soient établis
des relations récursives d'interaction entre les éléments
distingués et pourtant solidaires, qu'il s'agisse de l'objet et de
son environnement, de l'observé et de l'observateur, de la cause et
de l'effet, de l'interne et de l'externe, etc ... (OST, van de KERCHOVE
1993a : 201)
-34- (p 75-76) :
Le but du texte est de réfléchir les conditions de possibilité d'une constitution du temps social. Un temps social néguentropique (c'est-à-dire créateur), un temps humain chargé de sens. (...)
Entre l'immobilité du temps de l'éternité et la fugacité vide du temps qui fuit, se fait valoir la voie de la parole publique et de l'action politiques créatrices de mémoire organisée (Arendt). (...) Pour être capables d'histoire (Hegel), les sociétés doivent pouvoir féconder (faire interagir) la mémoire du passé par l'attente du futur et le projet par l'expérience (Ricoeur) (...) Pour ce faire, il s'impose de repenser les notions de génération, d'humanité et de patrimoine. Cette inscription dans une durée ne doit cependant pas se ramener (...) à la répétition du même. (...) Le temps d'une société ouverte est donc en partie indéterminée : c'est le temps de la praxis, distinct de celui de la fabrication programmée des objets (poiesis). Il faut le rappeler à l'encontre de toutes les philosophies politiques antidémocratiques qui voudraient bien remplacer l'agir (politique et collectif) par le faire (technocratique et élitiste). (...) Il faudra à la fois affirmer le droit de chacun à son propre rythme, et penser les conditions d'une harmonisation des temporalités qui ne se ramène pas au minutage du temps physique (planning-timing) et ne conduise pas à une mise au pas de toute la société (...)
Retour au point de départ ; d'un côté Kronos :
un pouvoir arbitraire, violent et solitaire associé à une
temporalité statique, sans passé ni avenir, sans
événement ni initiative, sans harmonisation de la pluralité
des rythmes ; de l'autre les Heures : symboles de l'harmonie dans
la Cité, associées (...) à une temporalité dynamique,
féconde (néguentropique), alternée et plurielle.
(OST 1997c : 1 and 3-4)
INTRODUCTION
-35- (p 81) :
Des Indous avaient amené un éléphant ; ils l'exhibèrent dans une maison obscure.
Plusieurs personnes entrèrent, une par une, dans le noir, afin de le voir.
Ne pouvant le voir des yeux, ils le tâtèrent de la main.
L'un posa la main sur sa trompe ; il dit : Cette créature est telle un tuyau d'eau.
L'autre lui toucha l'oreille : elle lui apparut semblable à un éventail.
Lui ayant saisi la jambe, un autre déclara : l'éléphant a forme de pilier.
Après lui avoir posé la main sur le dos, un autre dit : En vérité, cet éléphant est comme un trône.
De même, chaque fois que quelqu'un entendait une description de l'éléphant, il la comprenait d'après la partie qu'il avait touchée.
Leurs affirmations variaient selon ce qu'ils avaient perçu : l'un l'appelait dal, l'autre alîf .
Si chacun d'eux avait été muni d'une chandelle, leurs paroles n'auraient pas différé.
L'oeil de la perception est aussi limité que la paume de la main qui ne pouvait cerner la totalité (de l'éléphant).
L'oeil de la mer est une chose, l'écume en est une autre ; délaisse l'écume et regarde avec l'oeil de la mer.
Jour et nuit, provenant de la mer, se meuvent les flocons d'écume ; tu vois l'écume, non la mer. Que c'est étrange !
Nous nous heurtons les uns contre les autres comme des barques ; nos yeux sont aveuglés ; l'eau est pourtant claire.
O toi qui t'es endormi dans le bateau du corps, tu as vu l'eau ; contemple
l'Eau de l'eau. L'eau a une Eau qui la pousse, l'esprit un Esprit qui
l'appelle.
(de VITRAY-MEYEROVITCH 1995 : 23-24)
CHAPTER V
-36- (p 83) :
Nasrudin se mit à haranguer les gens sur la place du marché. Hé ! vous autres ! Voulez-vous la connaissance sans peine, le vrai sans le faux, la réalisation sans effort, le progrès sans sacrifice ?
En un clin d'oeil, une foule immense s'était assemblée autour de lui. Et tous de crier: Oui! oui !
Parfait ! dit le Mulla. Je voulais seulement me faire une idée. Si jamais je
découvre une chose pareille, vous pouvez compter sur moi pour n'en
rien vous cacher. (SHAH 1989: 125)
-37- (p 85) :
Toutes les traditions, qu'elles soient chrétienne, hindouiste,
judaïque, musulmane, bouddhique..., enseignent que la compréhension
de ce que nous sommes au niveau le plus profond est le point essentiel :
cette compréhension de la nature de l'esprit éclaire de
l'intérieur et illumine les enseignements de toutes les traditions.
Dans chacune d'elles, quiconque parvient à la compréhension
intime de l'esprit et en fait l'expérience immédiate aboutit
à une vision essentielle, sans commune mesure avec celle qu'il pouvait
avoir avant cette expérience directe. La connaissance de la nature
de l'esprit est la clef qui ouvre la compréhension de tous les
enseignements. Elle éclaire ce que nous sommes, la nature de toutes
nos expériences et révèle la forme la plus profonde
d'amour et de compassion. (KALOU RINPOCHE 1993 : 32)
-38- (p 86) :
Depuis des millénaires les humains ont pris l'habitude de s'arrêter sur la forme et l'apparence des choses en négligeant leur contenu et leur sens. C'est également ce qu'ils ont fait avec les Livres sacrés qui possèdent aussi une forme, un contenu et un sens. La forme, le récit est pour les gens ordinaires ; le contenu moral, symbolique, est pour les disciples qui essayent de l'approfondir et de le vivre ; quant au sens spirituel, il est pour les Initiés qui savent l'interpréter. (...)
Chaque forme, c'est-à-dire chaque chose ou chaque être qui
naît doit mourir et laisser la place à d'autres. Seul, l'esprit
qui n'a pas de commencement n'a pas de fin, et c'est lui qui s'incarne
successivement dans de nouvelles formes. Dieu n'a pas donné
l'éternité à la forme ; la forme est friable,
éphémère, elle ne peut résister au temps. Seul
le principe, l'esprit, qui appartient au monde divin, est indestructible,
éternel. (AIVANHOV 1994 : 11 and 26)
-39- (p 86) :
Un homme qui arrive à la vraie Sagesse ne voit pas Dieu comme
un être lointain, il ne Le sent pas hors de lui, mais en lui, dans
le fonds de son âme. Dieu est en tous, ceux qui Le cherchent Le trouvent
en eux. (HERBERT 1972 : 464)
-40- (p 86) :
Ce n'est qu'en sachant faire le détour qui consiste à utiliser
un miroir que nous pourrons voir notre face. De même que pour se se
voir lui-même l'oeil doit avoir recours à cet objet particulier,
l'esprit pour s'étudier lui-même doit faire appel à un
moyen particulier qui joue le rôle du miroir dans lequel il peut
découvrir son vrai visage : ce moyen est le dharma tel que nous le
transmet un guide spirituel. C'est dans la relation que nous entretenons
avec l'enseignement et cet ami spirituel ou ce guide que l'esprit va pouvoir
s'éveiller petit à petit à sa nature véritable
et finalement dépasser le paradoxe initial, en découvrant un
autre mode de connaissance. Cette découverte s'effectue dans diverses
pratiques, dites de méditation. (KALOU RINPOCHE 1993 : 46)
-41- (p 87) :
(...) pour répondre aux besoins divers des êtres et satisfaire
les dispositions, aspirations et tendances propres à chacun, il faut
une grande variété de philosophies, de religions et de traditions
spirituelles. Au vu de l'immense diversité des besoins de tous il
semble bien difficile qu'une seule religion convienne. Plus il y a de voies
spirituelles, mieux c'est! En même temps, il est certain que les
différentes croyances peuvent vivre en harmonie puisque l'éthique
fondamentale, universelle, est justement un terrain d'entente important.
Il suffira que les pratiquants de toutes ces voies apprennent à mieux
se connaître et qu'ils profitent de ce que les autres religions leur
enseignent pour améliorer leur pratique personnelle. (Le DALAI-LAMA
1994 : 84)
-42- (p 87) :
Vous savez qu'il y a des esprits de plusieurs catégories différentes. On peut être un matérialiste qui croit au bon sens et aux réalités terre à terre ; on peut ne pas s'intéresser aux formes et aux cérémonies ; on peut exiger des faits solides, qui résonnent et qui parlent à l'intelligence, et ne pas se contenter d'autre chose. Il y a aussi les puritains et les musulmans qui ne tolèrent dans les édifices consacrés au culte ni statue ni image. Fort bien, mais tel autre homme peut être plus artiste et avoir besoin d'un grand déploiement artistique, de belles lignes, de courbes gracieuses, (...) ; son esprit conçoit Dieu par ces formes extérieures tout comme votre esprit Le conçoit par l'intelligence. Il y a aussi l'homme de dévotion, de qui l'âme appelle Dieu éperdument ; sa seule idée est d'adorer Dieu et de chanter Ses louanges. Il y a encore le philosophe, qui se tient à l'écart de tous les autres et qui se moque d'eux. Quelles sottises, pense-t-il, quelles manières de concevoir Dieu!
Ils peuvent rire les uns des autres, mais chacun d'eux à sa place
dans ce monde. Tous ces esprits différents, tous ces types divers
sont nécessaires. S'il doit jamais y avoir une religion universelle,
il faudra qu'elle soit suffisamment vaste et large pour fournir à
chacun de ces esprits ce dont il a besoin. Il faudra qu'elle donne au philosophe
la force de la philosophie, à l'adorateur le coeur du dévot,
au ritualiste tout ce que peut fournir le symbolisme le plus merveilleux,
au poète autant de sentiment qu'il en pourra absorber, et encore autre
chose. Pour construire une religion assez vaste, il nous faudra revenir à
l'époque où les religions ont commencé et les embrasser
toutes. (VIVEKANANDA 1972: 374-375)
-43- (p 88) :
Il y a certains faits religieux qui, comme dans la science
matérielle, doivent être perçus, et c'est sur eux que
la religion sera construite. (...) Les sages du monde ont seulement le droit
de nous dire qu'ils ont analysé leur esprit, qu'ils y ont fait telle
et telle constatation, et que si nous agissons de même nous croirons
aussi, mais pas auparavant. C'est tout ce qu'il y a dans la religion.
(VIVEKANANDA 1972 : 136)
-44- (p 90-91) :
Chacun, ici-bas, est le Soi, à dire vrai infini. (...) Personne n'est éloigné du Soi. Par conséquent chacun est en Soi, c'est-à-dire réalisé. (...)
La réalisation consiste donc à rejeter l'idée fausse, que l'on n'est pas réalisé. La réalisation n'est pas quelque chose de nouveau à acquérir. Comme elle est permanente, elle doit donc exister de tout temps. Sinon, elle n'a aucune valeur.
Dès lors que l'idée erronée Je suis le corps
ou Je n'ai pas réalisé s'est dissipée, il
ne reste plus que la suprême Conscience, c'est-à-dire le Soi
auquel on donne le nom de réalisation pour satisfaire le niveau de
compréhension ordinaire des gens. Mais, en vérité, la
réalisation est éternelle, elle existe depuis toujours, à
présent et ici même. Finalement la réalisation revient
à éliminer l'ignorance et rien d'autre. (MAHARSHI 1993
: 417-418)
-45- (p 91) :
Depuis des milliers d'années que les hommes essaient de s'étudier pour connaître la structure de leur vie psychique, ils ont imaginé de nombreux modes de division. (...) Quel que soit le point de vue que l'on adopte, il est toujours véridique, cela dépend sous quel angle on regarde les choses.
Pour simplifier la question, nous dirons que l'être humain est une
unité parfaite, mais que cette unité est polarisée,
c'est-à-dire qu'elle se manifeste dans deux directions, sous deux
aspects différents. L'homme est fait de deux natures: la nature
inférieure et la nature supérieure, qui ont les même
facultés de penser, de sentir et d'agir, mais dans deux directions
contraires. J'ai appelé ces deux natures la personnalité et
l'individualité. (AIVANHOV 1984: 23-24)
-46- (p 92) :
La devise de tout bien-être, de tout bien moral est : Pas moi, mais toi.
(...) Oubliez-vous vous-même ; c'est la première leçon qu'il faille apprendre, que vous soyez religieux ou athée, agnostique ou védantiste, chrétien ou musulman. La grande leçon qui est évidente pour tous, c'est la destruction du petit moi et la construction du Moi Réel.
Deux forces ont travaillé côte à côte et parallèlement. L'une dit moi, l'autre dit pas moi. (...) d'un bout à l'autre de la création, ces deux forces travaillent côte à côte. Lorsque vous trouvez l'une, vous trouvez l'autre aussi. L'une est égoïsme, l'autre altruisme. L'une est acquisition, l'autre renoncement. L'une prend, l'autre donne.
(...) Y a-t-il quelqu'un qui pourrait nier que cet amour, ce
non-moi, cette renonciation est le seul pouvoir positif dans
le monde ? L'autre n'est qu'une utilisation mal dirigée du pouvoir
de l'amour (...) Un homme qui en assassine un autre a peut-être
été poussé à cet acte par l'amour qu'il porte
à son propre enfant. Son amour s'est limité à un petit
enfant et des millions d'autres êtres qui peuplent l'univers en ont
été exclus. Pourtant qu'il soit limité ou qu'il ne le
soit pas, c'est toujours le même amour. (VIVEKANANDA 1972 :
352-353)
-47- (p 93) :
(...) sucede que, según una de las más elementales reglas
de la lógica que ya hemos mencionado, las conclusiones fundamentadas
no pueden resultar más fuertes que las premisas fundantes
; por lo tanto, de una serie de afirmaciones acerca de la mera imanancia
- y por consiguiente, no absolutas - no pueden seguirse afirmaciones acerca
de derechos absolutos. (MASSINI-CORREAS 1991 : 268-269)
-48- (p 93-94) :
(...) las bases antropológicas de las más corrientes
fundamentaciones de los derechos humanos, no son las más
adecuadas para justificarlos racionalmente ; hay una evidente contradicción
entre unas teorias acerca del hombre eminentamente materialistas, fenomenistas
o empiristas y la afirmacion de que ese hombre tiene una especial
dignidad, que lo hace titular de derechos inalienables
de los que puede disponer con libertad. (MASSINI-CORREAS 1991 :
267-268)
-49- (p 97) :
Pour vivre, notre moi doit se soumettre à une croissance et un changement continuels de sa forme, ce que l'on pourrait appeler une mort continuelle et une vie continuelle qui se poursuivent parallèlement. (...) Ainsi la transformation embrasse à la fois changement et stabilité, pluralité et unité, mouvement et constance. Elle a la nature de la vie, c'est-à-dire qu'elle relie organiquement les pôles opposés, pierres d'achoppement de la logique, et qu'elle les réunit dans un rythme qui embrasse le tout. (...)
La trop grande importance attribuée à l'unité est une faute aussi grave que la trop grande importance attribuée à la dualité ou à la pluralité. Si nous concevons la dualité comme une opposition inconciliable entre deux principes indépendants qui s'excluent mutuellement et non comme la polarité nécessaire entre deux aspects mutuellement complémentaires de la réalité ou d'une unité supérieure - ou si nous nous attachons seulement à un côté, en excluant ou en niant complètement l'autre - nous sommes vraiment en proie à une sérieuse illusion. Si nous essayons de nier le fait de la polarité (en imaginant que la réalité consiste uniquement en l'unité), nous ne faisons que fermer les yeux à la réalité la plus évidente. (...)
Tout comme dans un orchestre chaque instrument joue sa propre partition mais trouve son accomplissement, sa réalisation suprême dans la coordination parfaite de tous les instruments et les rapports harmonieux entre eux, chaque conscience individuelle trouve son accomplissement dans un rapport parfait avec l'univers en toute sa variété de formes de vie et de forces individuelles, rapport qui ne permet ni immobilité ni stagnation.
Mais seul qui connaît l'ensemble de la partition peut jouer son rôle
à la perfection. Cela signifie qu'à moins de parvenir à
l'état d'illumination où de conscience universelle (...), à
moins d'atteindre cet état ultime nous ne pouvons pas trouver notre
accomplissement suprême. (GOVINDA 1993 : 184-185, 210-211 and
231)
CHAPTER VI
-50- (p 103) :
La vérité est une médaille dont un côté
est l'amour et l'autre la sagesse. Si vous cherchez la vérité
indépendamment de l'amour et de la sagesse, vous ne la trouverez pas.
Mais dès que vous possédez l'amour et la sagesse, que vous
cherchiez ou non la vérité, vous la possédez aussi.
(AIVANHOV 1970 : 222)
-51- (p 103) :
Ce qu'il nous faut maintenant, c'est combiner le coeur le plus grand
et l'intelligence la plus haute, l'amour infini et le savoir infini. Le
védântiste ne donne pas à Dieu d'autres attributs que
ces trois-ci : Il est Existence Infinie, Connaissance Infinie et Béatitude
Infinie, et le védântiste considère que ces trois ne
font qu'Un. L'existence sans la connaissance et sans l'amour ne saurait
être ; la connaissance sans l'amour et l'amour sans la connaissance
ne sauraient exister. Ce que nous voulons, c'est l'harmonie de l'Existence,
de la Connaissance et de la Béatitude Infinies. C'est cela notre
but. (VIVEKANANDA 1972 : 114)
-52- (p 103) :
Une paix profonde et sans limite, tel est l'Enseignement que j'ai
trouvé. (le BOUDDHA dans TRUNGPA 1981 : 31)
-53- (p 103) :
La paix est toujours présente. Vous n'avez qu'à écarter
les obstacles qui la troublent. Cette paix, c'est le Soi. (MAHARSHI
1993 : 416)
-54- (p 110-111)
Dès aujourd'hui, vous pouvez préparer votre avenir. Par le désir, par la pensée, par la prière, par l'imagination, vous choisissez la meilleure orientation, afin de vous manifester un jour comme des êtres de paix, de bonté, de lumière. Mais surtout, une fois cette orientation choisie, tâchez de vous y tenir. Apprenez à canaliser toutes vos énergies et à les orienter vers ce monde de l'harmonie et de l'amour. Même si quelques ombres apparaissent de temps en temps, cela ne durera pas : dans la mesure où vous maintenez intérieurement la bonne orientation, il arrivera un jour où vous ne dévierez plus. Voilà l'essentiel, et moi je ne m'occupe que de l'essentiel (...)
Quoi qu'il arrive, continuez à construire votre avenir, ne vous
découragez pas : vos souffrances, vos épreuves ne vous
apparaîtront bientôt que comme les vagues d'une tempête
au-dessus desquelles vous planez. S'il vous arrive de vous sentir
écrasé par les épreuves, c'est que vous n'avez pas su
garder une échappée sur votre avenir lumineux. Votre horizon
est bouché, mais il est bouché parce que c'est vous qui l'avez
bouché, et il ne tient qu'à vous d'ouvrir une fenêtre
pour voir le soleil. (AIVANHOV 1997 : 270-271)
-55- (p 111) :
L'arc-en-ciel doit sa beauté aux tons variés de ses couleurs. De même, nous considérons les voix des divers croyants qui s'élèvent de tous les points de la terre comme une symphonie de louanges à l'adresse de Dieu qui ne peut être qu'Unique.
Nous déplorons amèrement la méprise de certains religieux
(...) qui les amène souvent à rejeter comme discordant l'hymne
de leur voisin. Pour lutter contre cette tendance, frère en Dieu,
quelle que soit la religion ou la congrégation à laquelle tu
es affilié, médite longuement sur ce verset :
ABOU Sélim, 1992, Cultures et droits de l'homme,
Mesnil-sur-l'Estrée, Hachette, Col. Pluriel, Série Intervention,
140 p
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1968, La paix, Les puissances
de la vie, France, Prosveta, 1980, 264 p (229-264)
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1970, Les deux faces de la Vérité
: L'Amour et la Sagesse, Connais-toi toi-même
- jnani yoga, France, Prosveta, Col. Oeuvres complètes, 1994,
270 p (222-226)
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1972, Le tableau synoptique,
Connais-toi toi-même - jnani yoga, France, Prosveta,
Col. Oeuvres complètes, 1994, 270 p (13-33)
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1984, Nature humaine et nature divine,
Fréjus, Prosveta, Col. Izvor, 167 p
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1985, L'homme à la conquète
de sa destinée, Fréjus, Prosveta, Col. Izvor, 196 p
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1992, La vérité, fruit de
la sagesse et de l'amour, France, Prosveta, Col. Izvor, 213 p
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1994, Une philosophie de l'Universel,
France, Prosveta, Col. Izvor, 187 p
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1995, Qu'est-ce qu'un Maître spirituel
?, France, Prosveta, Col. Izvor, 192 p
AIVANHOV Omraam Mikhaël, 1997, Vous êtes des dieux - Psaumes
82: 6, Evangile de St Jean 10: 34, France, Prosveta, 570 p
ALLIOT Michel, 1968, L'acculturation juridique,
POIRIER Jean (ed.), Encyclopédie de la Pléiade - Ethnologie
Générale, Belgique, Gallimard, 1907 p (1180-1246)
ALLIOT Michel, 1980a, Modèles sociétaux- 1. Les
communautés, 1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions
à des colloques, textes du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris,
LAJP, p 156-162
ALLIOT Michel, 1980b, Un droit nouveau est-il en train de naitre
en Afrique?, CONAC Gérard (éd.), Dynamiques et
finalités des droits africains - Actes du colloque de la Sorbonne
La vie du Droit en Afrique, Paris, Economica, Col. Recherches
Panthéon-Sorbonne Université de Paris I, Série Sciences
juridiques, 509 p (467-495)
ALLIOT Michel, 1981, Protection de la personne et structure sociale (Europe et Afrique), 1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions à des colloques, textes du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p 169-187
ALLIOT Michel, 1983a, Les transferts de droit ou la double illusion,
1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions à des colloques, textes
du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p 188-198
ALLIOT Michel, 1983b, Anthropologie et juristique - Sur les conditions
d'élaboration d'une science du droit, 1953-1989 Recueil
d'articles, contributions à des colloques, textes du Recteur Michel
Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p 207-241
ALLIOT Michel, 1983c, L'anthropologie juridique et le droit des
manuels, 1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions à des
colloques, textes du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p
251-268
ALLIOT Michel, 1984, La coutume dans les droits originellement
africains, 1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions à
des colloques, textes du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p
269-290
ALLIOT Michel, 1986a, Individu et dépendances: la
problématique des droits de l'homme dans le monde
méditerrannéen et en Afrique, 1953-1989 Recueil
d'articles, contributions à des colloques, textes du Recteur Michel
Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p 291-308
ALLIOT Michel, 1986b, Droits de l'homme et anthropologie du droit,
1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions à des colloques, textes
du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris, LAJP, p 313-320
ALLIOT Michel, 1995, Droits de l'homme et autres traditions,
Le Courrier de Juristes-Solidarités, Septembre, n°10,
p 1 et 6
ANAND R.P., 1983, Origins and development of the law of the sea - History
of International Law Revisited, The Hague/Boston/London, Martinus Nijhoff,
243 p
AN-NA'IM Abdullahi Ahmed, 1990, Human Rights in the Muslim World :
Socio-Political Conditions and Scriptural Imperatives - A Preliminary
Inquiry, ALSTON Philip (ed.), Human Rights Law, Great Britain,
Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series,
1996, 559 p (253-292)
ARCHER Margaret S., 1996, Theory, Culture and Post-Industrial
Society, FEATHERSTONE Mike (ed.), Global Culture - Nationalism,
Globalization and modernity, Great Britain, Sage Publications, A Theory,
Culture & Society special issue, 411 p (97-119)
ARNAUD André-Jean, 1990, Repenser un droit pour l'époque
post-moderne, Le Courrier du CNRS, Avril, n° 75, p 81-82
ARNAUD André-Jean, 1991, Pour une pensée juridique
européenne, Vendôme, PUF, Col. Les Voies du Droit, 304 p
ATLAN Henri, 1986, A tort et à raison Intercritique de la science
et du mythe, Evreux, Seuil, Col. Science Ouverte, 443 p
ATLAN Henri, 1996, The frontiers of science, The UNESCO
Courier, Mars, p 4-7
AURENCHE G., COLLANGE J.F., 1990, Christianisme et Droits de
l'Homme, LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions
universelles des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles
et intellectuelles des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p
(113-139)
BA Amadou Hampaté, 1994, Vie et enseignement de Tierno Bokar,
Tours, Seuil, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 254 p
BADIE Bertrand, 1995a, L'Etat importé - L'occidentalisation
de l'ordre politique, Mesnil-sur-l'Estrée, Fayard, Col. L'espace
du politique, 334 p
BADIE Bertrand, 1995b, La fin des territoires - Essai sur le
désordre international et sur l'utilité sociale du respect,
France, Fayard, Col. L'espace du politique, 276 p
BAUER Robert, 1996, Brüchige Strukturen - Theoretische Grundlagen
postmoderner Organisationsforschung, Linz, Universitätsverlag Rudolf
Trauner, 301 p
BAUMAN Zygmunt, 1996, Modernity and Ambivalence, FEATHERSTONE
Mike (ed.), Global Culture - Nationalism, Globalization and modernity,
Great Britain, Sage Publications, A Theory, Culture & Society special
issue, 411 p (143-169)
BIELEFELDT Heiner, 1993, Die Beheimatung der Menschenrechte in
unterschiedlichen Kulturen, BIELEFELDT Heiner, DEILE Volkmar, THOMSEN
Bernd (eds.), Amnesty International: Menschenrecht vor der
Jahrtausendwende, Frankfurt am Main, Fischer, 253 p (165-184)
BIRKE Adolf M.,1994, Das Problem der Menschenrechte - Eine historische
Einführung, ODERSKY Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte : Herkunft
- Geltung - Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220 p (9-22)
BOCK Eleonore, 1993, Die Mystik in den Religionen der Welt - Hinduismus.
Buddhismus. Judaismus. Islam. Christentum., Augsburg, Goldmann, 491p
BOLTANSKI Luc, THEVENOT Laurent, 1983, Finding one's way in social
space: a study based on games, Social Science Information, vol.
22 (4-5), p 631-680
BOLTANSKI Luc, THEVENOT Laurent, 1991, De la justification - Les
économies de la grandeur, Mesnil-sur-l'Estrée, Gallimard,
Col. nrf essais, 483 p
BOURDIEU Pierre, 1980, Le sens pratique, Lonrai, Les Editions de Minuit,
Col. Le sens commun, 474 p
BOURDIEU Pierre, 1986, Habitus, code et codification, Actes
de la recherche en sciences sociales, n° 64, Septembre, p 40-44
BOUTROS-GHALI Boutros, 1993, Discours du Secrétaire
général de l'Organisation des Nations Unies à l'ouverture
de la Conférence mondiale sur les droits de l'homme, doc.
A/CONF.157/22, 12 Juillet, 15 p
BRELET Claudine, 1995, Anthropologie de l'ONU - Utopie et Fondation,
C.E.E., L'Harmattan, 230 p
CABANILLAS Renato Rabbi-Baldi, 1991, Las revoluciones francesa y
norteamericana ante los derechos humanos. Un intento de
armonización., Persona y Derecho - Suplemento Humana Iura
de derechos humanos 1, p 299-314
CAILLÉ Alain, 1992, Sujets individuels et sujet collectif,
Centre Georges Pompidou (ed.), Philosophie et anthropologie, Paris,
Centre Pompidou, Col. Espace international. Philosophie, 190 p (93-114)
CAPRA Fritjof, 1992, The Tao of Physics - An exploration of the parallels
between modern physics and Eastern mysticism, Great Britain, Flamingo,
412 p
CASTORIADIS Cornelius, 1992, L'institution imaginaire de la
société, Aubin à Ligugé, Seuil, cinquième
édition revue et corrigée, Col. Esprit, 497 p
CHENIQUE François, 1996, Sagesse chrétienne et mystique
orientale, Clamecy, Dervy, 654 p
CHIBA Masaji, 1987, Three Dichotomies of Law - An Analytical Scheme
of Legal Culture, Tokai Law Review, n° 1, p 290-279
CHIBA Masaji, 1989, Three Dichotomies of Law in Pluralism, SACK
Peter, ALECK Jonathan (eds.), Law and Anthropology, Great Britain,
Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series,
1992, 527 p (415-424)
CHOI Dai-Kwon, 1980, Western Law in a Traditional Society Korea,
VARGA Csaba, Comparative Legal Cultures, Great Britain, Dartmouth,
The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1992,
614 p (249-274)
CHOURAQUI J.M., 1990, Des devoirs aux Droits de l'Homme : une perspective
juive, LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions
universelles des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles
et intellectuelles des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p
(81-112)
CONAC Gérard, 1980, La vie du droit en Afrique, CONAC
Gérard (éd.), Dynamiques et finalités des droits
africains - Actes du colloque de la Sorbonne La vie du Droit en
Afrique, Paris, Economica, Col. Recherches Panthéon-Sorbonne
Université de Paris I, Série: Sciences juridiques, 509 p (V-XXXX)
CONAC Gérard, 1990, Le juge de l'Etat en Afrique francophone,
Afrique Contemporaine, 4e trimestre, n° 156 (spécial),
p 13-20
CONAC Gérard, AMOR Abdelfattah (eds.), 1994, Islam et droits de
l'homme, Paris, Economica, Col. La Vie du Droit en Afrique, 97 p
CONFUCIUS, 1981, Entretiens de Confucius - Traduit du chinois par Anne
Cheng, France, Seuil, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 153 p
COTTERRELL Roger, 1989, The Politics of Jurisprudence - A Critical
Introduction to Legal Philosophy, London and Edinburgh, Butterworths,
277 p
COTTERRELL Roger, 1992, The Sociology of Law : An Introduction, Great
Britain, Butterworths, 398 p
COTTERRELL Roger, 1996a, Law's Community - Legal Theory in Sociological
Perspective, USA, Oxford University Press, Oxford Socio-Legal Studies
Series, 381 p
COTTERRELL Roger, 1996b, The Rule of Law in Transition : Revisisting
Franz Neumann's Sociology of Legality, Social & Legal Studies,
Volume 5, n° 4, December, p 451-470
COTTERRELL Roger, 1996c, A Legal Concept of Community, Draft
paper, 17 p
COULSON Noel James, 1959, Muslim Custom and Case-Law, EDGE Ian
(ed.), Islamic Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The
International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 608
p (259-270)
DAGPO-RIMPOCHE, 1990, Les Droits de l'Homme vus par un Bouddhiste,
LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions universelles
des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles et intellectuelles
des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p (175-188)
Le DALAI-LAMA, 1994, Au-delà des dogmes, Mayenne, Albin Michel,
Col. Spiritualités vivantes, 288 p
DELMAS-MARTY Mireille, 1994, Pour un droit commun, Paris, Seuil, Col.
La Librairie du XXe Siècle, 305 p
DONNELLY Jack, 1982, Human Rights and Human Dignity : An Analytic Critique
of Non-Western Conceptions of Human Rights, ALSTON Philip (ed.), Human
Rights Law, Great Britain, Dartmouth,The International Library of Essays
in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 559 p (147-160)
DORE Francis, 1990, L'Inde, l'Hindouisme et l'égalité,
LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions universelles
des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles et intellectuelles
des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p (189-209)
DREYFUS Georges, 1992, La vacuité selon l'école Madhyamika
et présentation des autres écoles, Marzens, Vajra Yogini,
155 p
DUMONT Louis, 1979, Homo hierarchicus - Le système des castes et
ses implications, Saint-Amand (Cher), Gallimard, Col. Tel, 449 p
DUMONT Louis, 1991, Essais sur l'individualisme - Une perspective
anthropologique sur l'idéologie moderne, Saint Amand (Cher), Seuil,
3e éd., Col. Points, Série Essais, 310 p
EBERHARD Christoph, 1994, Die Bedeutung des Abstraktionsprinzips anhand
des Vergleichs zwischen dem deutschen und dem französischen
Kaufvertragsrecht., Magister Legum (LL.M.) Thesis with Professor C.-W.
Canaris, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München, 63 p
EBERHARD Christoph, 1996, De l'universalisme à l'universalité
des droits de l'homme par le dialogue interculturel - Un défi de sortie
de modernité, Mémoire de DEA Études
Africaines Option Anthropologie Juridique et Politique sous la
direction de M. Etienne Le Roy, Université de Paris I - Panthéon
Sorbonne, 95 p, consultable au LAJP
EBERHARD Christoph, 1997, Droits de l'Homme - Vers une communauté
comme écosystème ?, Draft paper, 7 p
FEATHERSTONE Mike, 1996, Global Culture : An Introduction,
FEATHERSTONE Mike (ed.), Global Culture - Nationalism, Globalization and
modernity, Great Britain, Sage Publications, A Theory, Culture &
Society special issue, 411 p (1-14)
FINNIS John, 1996, Natural Law and Natural Rights, Hong Kong, Oxford
University Press, Clarendon Law Series, 425 p
FOBLETS Marie-Claire, 1992, Le droit face au pluralisme: 1. Théorie
du pluralisme juridique; 2. Le statut des minorités, Bulletin
de liaison du LAJP, Juin, n° 17, p 21-26
FOBLETS Marie-Claire, 1993, Enchevetrement des systèmes juridiques
en Europe occidentale: passé, présent et avenir,
Bulletin de Liaison du LAJP, Juin, n° 18, p 19-23
FUNK David A., 1988, Traditional Orthodox Hindu Jurisprudence : Justifying
Dharma and Danda, NANDA Ved P., SINHA Surya Prakash (eds.), Hindu
Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library
of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 357 p (27-71)
GHAI Yash, 1994, Human Rights and Governance : The Asia Debate,
ALSTON Philip (ed.), Human Rights Law, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The
International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 559
p (219-252)
GOONATILAKE Susantha, 1993, Future of Asian Cultures: Between Localization
and Globalization, MASINI Eleonora Barbieri, ATAL Yogesh (eds.),
Perspectives on Asia's Futures III: the futures of Asian Culture (Report
of UNESCO Third Meeting on Perspectives on Asia's Futures III, Bangkok, 8-11
February 1993), Bangkok, UNESCO Principal Regional Office for Asia and
the Pacific, Social and Human Sciences in Asia and the Pacific. RUSHSAP Series
of Monograph and Occasional Papers 38, 159 p (131-159)
GOULET Denis, 1984, Some Complementary Remarks,
Interculture, Vol. XVII, n° 2, Cahier 83, p 63-66
GOVINDA Lama Anagarika, 1976, Les fondements de la mystique
tibétaine, France, Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes,
Série Bouddhisme, 440 p
GOVINDA Lama Anagarika, 1993, La méditation créatrice,
France, Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes, 309 p
GREENHOUSE Carol J., 1989, Just in Time : Temporality and the Cultural
Legitimation of Law, SACK Peter, ALECK Jonathan (eds.), Law and
Anthropology, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of
Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1992, 527 p (319-339)
GUENON René, 1994, La crise du monde moderne, Saint-Amand (Cher),
Gallimard, Col. Folio/Essais, 201 p
HALEVI Z'ev ben Shimon, 1993, Der Weg der Kabbalah, Germany, Knaur,
313 p
HALEY John O., 1982, Sheathing the Sword of Justice in Japan : An Essay
on Law Without Sanctions, FUJIKURA Koichiro (ed.), Japanese Law
and Legal Theory, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library
of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 647 p (299-281)
HALLAQ Wael B., 1984, Was the Gate of Ijtihad Closed ?, EDGE
Ian (ed.), Islamic Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain, Aldershot,The
International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 608
p (287-325)
HART H.L.A., 1994, The Concept of Law, Great Britain, Oxford University
Press, Clarendon Law Series, Second edition, 315 p
HERBERT Jean, 1972, L'enseignement de Râmakrishna, Saint-Amand (Cher), Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes, Série Hindouisme, 604 p
HERBERT, Jean, 1979, La mythologie hindoue - son message, France,
Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes, Série Hindouisme,
491 p
HERBERT Jean, 1988, Spiritualité hindoue, Saint-Amand (Cher),
Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes, Série Hindouisme,
573 p
HERVADA Javier, 1991, Los derechos inherentes a la dignidad de la persona
humana, Persona y Derecho - Suplemento Humana Iura de derechos humanos
1, p 345-379
HESSELING Gerti, LE ROY Etienne, 1990, Le Droit et ses pratiques,
Politique Africaine, Décembre, n° 40, p 2-11
HÖFFE Otfried, 1994, Die Menschenrechte im interkulturellen
Diskurs, ODERSKY Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte : Herkunft - Geltung
- Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220 p (119-137)
HUAKARA T., 1990, Les fondements des Droits de l'Homme en Afrique,
LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions universelles
des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles et intellectuelles
des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p (237-251)
IMBERT J., 1990, Approche de la déclaration française
des Droits de l'homme et du citoyen, LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK
K. (eds.), Les dimensions universelles des Droits de l'Homme - Volume
I : Les dimensions spirituelles et intellectuelles des Droits de l'Homme,
Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p (25-50)
JOUAN Marie-Pierre, Droits de l'enfant : quelle pertinence pour l'enfant
marginalisé dans l'espace urbain ? Analyse à partir
d'expériences en France, à Chicago et en Afrique du Sud,
TESSIER Stéphane (ed.), L'enfant des rues et son univers - ville,
socialisation et marginalité, France, Syros, 227 p (95-103)
JUNG C.G., 1986, Selected writings Introduced by Anthony Storr, Grande
Bretagne, Fontana Press, 447 p
JUNG C.G., 1994, Psychologie et Alchimie, France, Buchet/Chastel,
705 p
KALOU RINPOCHE, 1993, La voie du bouddha, Evreux, Seuil, Col. Points,
Série Sagesses, 423 p
KAUSIKAN Bilahari, 1993, Asia's Different Standard, ALSTON Philip
(ed.), Human Rights Law, Great Britain, Dartmouth,The International
Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 559 p (201-218)
KAYA Jean Pierre, 1995, Initiation et développement du système
communautaire, Bulletin de liaison du LAJP, Juin, p 86-97
van de KERCHOVE Michel, OST François, 1992, Le droit ou les paradoxes
du jeu, Vendôme, PUF, 1992, Col. Les voies du droit, 268 p
KILANI Mondher, 1994a, Introduction à l'anthropologie, Lausanne,
Payot, 368 p
KILANI Mondher, 1994b, L'invention de l'autre, Dijon-Quetigny,
Payot Lausanne, 318p
KIM Chin, LAWSON Craig M., 1979, The Law of the Subtle Mind : The
Traditional Japanese Conception of Law, VARGA Csaba (ed.), Comparative
Legal Cultures, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of
Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1992, 614 p (275-513)
KOTHARI Rajni, 1987, Human Rights - A movement In Search Of A
Theory, ALSTON Philip (ed.), Human Rights Law, Great Britain,
Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series,
1996, 559 p (189-199)
KOYRE Alexandre, 1986, Théologie et science, De la
mystique à la science - Cours, conférences et documents 1922-1962
- Edités par Pietro Redondi, Editions de l'Ecole des Hautes Etudes
en Sciences Sociales, Dijon-Quetigny, 227p (180-197)
KRISHNA Gopi, 1994, Kundalini - The secret of Yoga, Delhi, UBS Publishers'
Distributors Ltd., 214 p
KRYGIER Martin, 1986, Law as a Tradition, Law and
Philosophy, n° 5, p 237-262
KUHN Thomas S., 1994, La structure des révolutions scientifiques,
Manchecourt, Flammarion, Col. Champs, 284 p
KUYU Camille Mwissa, 1995, Droits et vécu juridique réel
des enfants marginalisés : pour une compatibilité des
systèmes normatifs, TESSIER Stéphane (ed.), L'enfant
des rues et son univers - ville, socialisation et marginalité,
France, Syros, 227 p (79-93)
KYMLICKA Will, 1989, Liberalism, Community and Culture, Great Britain,
Clarendon Press . Oxford, Clarendon Paperbacks, 280 p
KYMLICKA Will, 1995, Multicultural Citizenship - A Liberal Theory of Minority
Rights, Great Britain, Clarendon Press . Oxford, Oxford Political Theory
Series, 280 p
LACEY Nicola, 1996, Community in Legal Theory : Idea, Ideal or
Ideology?, Studies in Law, Politics and Society, Vol. 15, p
105-146
LAO-TZEU, 1979, La Voie et sa vertu - Tao-tê-king - Texte chinois
présenté et traduit par François Houang et Pierre
Leyris, France, Seuil, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 181 p
LATOUCHE Serge, 1991, La planète des naufragés - Essai sur
l'après-développement, Saint-Amand (Cher), La Découverte,
Col. Essais, 235 p
LATOUCHE Serge, 1992, L'occidentalisation du monde, Paris, La
Découverte, Col. Agalma, 143 p
LEDURE Yves, 1994, Aufklärung und Menschenrechte, ODERSKY
Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte : Herkunft - Geltung -
Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220 p (138-144)
LEE Luke T., LAI Whalen W., 1978, The Chinese Conceptions of Law :
Confucian, Legalist, and Buddhist, VARGA Csaba (ed.), Comparative
Legal Cultures, Great Britain, Dartmouth,The International Library of
Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1992, 614 p (225-247)
LENOBLE Jacques, OST François, 1980, Prolégomènes
à une lecture épistémologique des modèles
juridiques, Domination ou partage ? Développement endogène
et transfert des connaissances, Paris, UNESCO, 1980, p 79-91
LEPENIES Wolf, 1996, Le fondamentalisme occidental est
dépassé, Le Monde, Samedi 17 Février, p
13
LE ROY Etienne, 1984, Le Diable et les droits de l'homme,
Interculture, Vol. XVII, n°1 et 2, Cahier 83, p 67-73
LE ROY Etienne, 1988a, Le pluralisme juridique dans le creuset de la
démocratie : l'exemplaire Sénégal, LE ROY Etienne,
L'analyse de processus et la gestion urbaine à Thies, M'Bour et
Richard Toll (Senegal), Paris, Université de Paris I
Panthéon-Sorbonne, Centre d'études juridiques comparatives,
107 p (30-58)
LE ROY Etienne, 1988b, La domestication du Léviathan ou l'envers
du Droit - Trente ans de pratiques juridiques à l'ombre de l'Etat
en Afrique francophone, Contribution au colloque franco-britannique
Les Afriques francophones depuis l'indépendance, Oxford
(G.B.) 29-30 Avril
LE ROY Etienne, 1990a, Juristique et anthropologie : Un pari sur
l'avenir, Journal of legal pluralism and unofficial law, number
29, p 5-21
LE ROY Etienne, 1990b, Le justiciable africain et la redécouverte
d'une voie négociée de règlement des conflits,
Afrique Contemporaine, 4e trimestre, n° 156 (spécial),
p 111-120
LE ROY Etienne, 1991, Les usages politiques du droit, COULON
Christian, MARTIN Denis-Constant (éds.), Les afriques politiques,
Saint-Amand (Cher), La Découverte, Col. Textes à l'appui,
Série Histoire contemporaine, 294 p (109-122)
LE ROY Etienne, 1992a, Droits humains et développement : des
visions du monde à concilier, recueil des articles de E. Le
Roy consultable au LAJP (B 92-9)
LE ROY Etienne, 1992b, Les fondements anthropologiques des droits de
l'homme - Crise de l'universalisme et post modernité, Revue
de la recherche juridique Droit prospectif , N° XVII - 48 (17ème
année- 48e numéro)
LE ROY Etienne, 1992c, Un droit peut en cacher un autre,
Informations sociales, Mars, n° 22, p 10-19
LE ROY Etienne, 1992d, A la recherche d'une conception
africaine de l'Etat de Droit?, Contribution au colloque
Processus de démocratisation en Afrique et en France, Paris, Fondation
pour les études de défense nationale, 19 et 20 mai, 15 p
LE ROY Etienne, 1992e, L'adieu au droit coutumier, RUDE-ANTOINE
Edwige (ed.), L'immigration face aux lois de la République,
CEE, Karthala, 207 p (20-33)
LE ROY Etienne, 1993a, De la norme à la pratique du droit,
construire le droit, Bulletin de Liaison du LAJP, Juin, p
64-71
LE ROY Etienne, 1993b, Enjeux de la post-modernité, LE
ROY E., VON TROTHA Tr. (éds.), La violence et l'état - Formes
et évolution d'un monopole - Textes rassemblés et
présentés par J. LOMBARD, Mondeville, L'Harmattan, 272
p (235-242)
LE ROY Etienne, 1993c, Les recherches sur le droit interne des pays en développement - Du droit du développement à la définition pluraliste de l'Etat de droit, CHOQUET C., DOLLFUS. O, LE ROY E., VERNIERES M. (éds.), Etat des savoirs sur le développement - Trois décennies de sciences sociales en langue française, Paris, Karthala, 229 p (75-86)
LE ROY Etienne, 1994a, Le recours au judiciaire dans le cadre de la
protection des jeunes - Mythes et réalités, recueil des
articles de E. Le Roy consultable au LAJP, 1994
LE ROY Etienne, 1994b, Les droits de l'homme, entre un universalisme
hâtif et le ghetto des particularismes culturels, recueil des
articles de E. Le Roy consultable au LAJP, 1994 fin
LE ROY Etienne, 1995a, L'accès à l'universalisme par
le dialogue interculturel, Revue générale de droit, vol.
26, p 5-26
LE ROY Etienne, 1995b, La médiation mode d'emploi, Droit
et Société, n° 29, p 39-55
LE ROY Etienne, 1995c, 'Espace public' et 'socialisation' dans les
métropoles: quelques préliminaires à une problématique
interculturelle, TESSIER Stéphane (ed.), L'enfant des rues
et son univers - ville, socialisation et marginalité, France,
Syros, 227 p (31-45)
LE ROY Etienne, 1996a, L'hypothèse du multijuridisme dans un
contexte de sortie de modernité, consultable au LAJP, 13 p
LE ROY Etienne, 1996b, Prolégomènes à une analyse
dynamique de la gestion foncière, LE ROY Etienne, KARSENTY Alain,
BERTRAND Alain (eds.), La sécurisation foncière en Afrique
- Pour une Gestion viable des ressources renouvelables, Clamecy, Karthala,
388 p (185-211)
LE ROY Etienne, 1996c, L'ordre négocié - A propos d'un
concept en émergence, GÉRARD Philippe, OST François,
van de KERCHOVE Michel (eds.), Droit négocié, Droit imposé
?, Bruxelles, Publications des Facultés Universitaires Saint-Louis,
p 341-351
LE ROY Etienne, 1997a, Les fondements anthropologiques et philosophiques
des droits de l'homme - L'universalité des droits humains peut-elle
être fondée sur le principe de la complémentarité
des différences ?, Sommaire de l'enseignement donné pour
la 28ème session de l'Institut International des Droits de l'Homme
de Strasbourg, 16 p
LE ROY Etienne, 1997b, Sortir d'une représentation injuste de
l'enfant des banlieues - Approches anthropologiques des parcours d'insertion
et de socialisation des jeunes, SOULÉ Michel, GOLSE Bernard
(eds.), C'est pas juste! L'éthique des enfants devant les actes
des adultes - La notion de justice et d'injustice chez l'enfant, Paris,
ESF, Col. La vie de l'enfant, 117 p (73-84)
LE ROY Etienne, 1997c, La face cachée du complexe normatif en
Afrique noire francophone, ROBERT Philippe, SOUBIRAN-PAILLET Francine,
van de KERCHOVE Michel (eds.), Normes, Normes juridiques, Normes pénales
- Pour une sociologie des frontières - Tome I, CEE, L'Harmattan,
Col. Logiques Sociales, Série Déviance/GERN, 353 p (123-138)
LE ROY Etienne, 1997d, Crises, mondialisation, complexité sociale
- Spécificités des situations et généralités
des pratiques, consultable au LAJP, 13 p
LE ROY Etienne, 1997e, Logique institutionnelle et logique fonctionnelle,
de l'opposition à la complémentarité, consultable
au LAJP, 10 p
LÊ THÀNH KHÔI, 1992, Culture, créativité
et développement, Condé-sur-Noireau, L'Harmattan, Col.
Espaces Interculturels, 223 p
LEVI-STRAUSS Claude, 1980, Anthropologie structurale deux,
Dijon-Quetigny, Plon, 450 p
LIE Rico, 1997, Globalization and Localization in Culture and
Communication, paper for the international conference on Media
and Politics, 27-28 February - 1 March 1997, Katholieke Universiteit
Brussel, Brussels, 44 p
LINZHENG Qin, 1993, Selection and Reconstruction: Cultural Change in
Asia, MASINI Eleonora Barbieri, ATAL Yogesh (eds.), Perspectives
on Asia's Futures III: the futures of Asian Culture (Report of UNESCO Third
Meeting on Perspectives on Asia's Futures III, Bangkok, 8-11 February
1993), Bangkok, UNESCO Principal Regional Office for Asia and the Pacific,
Social and Human Sciences in Asia and the Pacific. RUSHSAP Series of Monograph
and Occasional Papers 38, 159 p (81-93)
LONG S., 1990, L'église d'Angleterre et les Droits de
l'Homme, LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions
universelles des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles
et intellectuelles des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p
(141-147)
MacCORMACK G., 1978, Anthropology and Legal Theory, SACK Peter,
ALECK Jonathan (eds.), Law and Anthropology, Great Britain, Dartmouth,
The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1992,
527 p (113-129)
MacCORMICK Neil, 1993, Beyond the Sovereign State, The Modern
Law Review, January, Vol. 56, n° 1, p 1-18
MAHARSHI Ramana, 1993, L'enseignement de Ramana Maharshi,
Saint-Amand-Montrond (Cher), Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes,
602 p
MAIER Hans, 1994, Christentum und Menschenrechte - Historische
Umrisse, ODERSKY Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte: Herkunft - Geltung
- Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220 p (49-64)
MARCUS George, 1992, Past, present and emergent identities : requirements
for ethnographies of late twentieth-century modernity worldwide, LASH
Scott, FRIEDMAN Jonathan, Modernity and Identity, Great Britain,
Blackwell, 379 p (309-330)
MARTIN Nuria Belloso, 1995, Planteamientos doctrinales de los derechos
humanos a través de la historia., Persona y Derecho - Suplemento
Humana Iura de derechos humanos 5, p 51-91
MARUYAMA Magoroh, 1996, Dis-moi comment tu penses, Le Courrier
de l'UNESCO, Février, p 31-35
MASSINI-CORREAS Carlos Ignacio, 1991, El pensamiento contemporáneo
acerca de los derechos humanos (ensayo de caracterización),
Persona y Derecho - Suplemento Humana Iura de derechos humanos 1,
p 255-273
MAUSS Marcel, 1995, Une catégorie de l'esprit humain : la notion
de personne, celle de 'Moi', Sociologie et anthropologie,
Vendôme, PUF, Col. Quadrige, p 333-362
MAYOR Federico, 1995, Allocution de M. Federico Mayor, Directeur
général de l'Organisation des Nations Unies pour l'éducation,
la science et la culture (UNESCO): Conférence en hommage à
Rajiv Gandhi Les cultures dans le village planétaire: courtoisie
ou conformité?, New Delhi, 1er Mai 1995, Transcription
du discours, 6 p
MAYOR Federico, 1996, The rights of future generations,The
UNESCO Courier, Mars, p 36-37
MOORE Sally Falk, 1973, Law and Social Change : The Semi-Autonomous
Social Field as an Appropriate Subject of Study, Law and Society
Review, Summer, p 719-746
MOORE Sally Falk, 1983, Law as Process - An Anthropological Approach,
Great Britain, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 263 p
MORGENSTERN Christian, 1973, Gesammelte Werke. In einem Band,
München, R. Piper & Co. Verlag, 615 p
MORIN Edgar, 1992, La méthode 3. La connaissance de la
connaissance, Manchecourt, Seuil, Col. Points, Série Essais, 243
p
MORIN Edgar, 1995, La méthode 4. Les idées, Manchecourt,
Seuil, Col. Points, Série Essais, 261 p
MORIN Edgar, 1996, Pour une réforme de la pensée,
Le Courrier de l'UNESCO, Février, p 10-14
MUSHAKOJI Kinhide, 1993, Post-Modern Cultural Development in East Asia:
Beyond the JapaNIEs Version of Confucianism, MASINI Eleonora Barbieri,
ATAL Yogesh (eds.), Perspectives on Asia's Futures III: the futures of
Asian Culture (Report of UNESCO Third Meeting on Perspectives on Asia's Futures
III, Bangkok, 8-11 February 1993), Bangkok, UNESCO Principal Regional
Office for Asia and the Pacific, Social and Human Sciences in Asia and the
Pacific. RUSHSAP Series of Monograph and Occasional Papers 38, 159 p
(57-80)
NANDA Ved P., 1995, Hinduism and Human Rights, NANDA Ved P.,
SINHA Surya Prakash (eds.), Hindu Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain,
Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series,
1996, 357 p (237-247)
NANDI Ashis, DESHINGKAR Giri, 1993, The Future of Cultures: An Asian
Perspective, MASINI Eleonora Barbieri, ATAL Yogesh (eds.),
Perspectives on Asia's Futures III: the futures of Asian Culture (Report
of UNESCO Third Meeting on Perspectives on Asia's Futures III, Bangkok, 8-11
February 1993), Bangkok, UNESCO Principal Regional Office for Asia and
the Pacific, Social and Human Sciences in Asia and the Pacific. RUSHSAP Series
of Monograph and Occasional Papers 38, 159 p (25-35)
NINO Carlos Santiago, 1994, Positivism and Communitarianism : Between
Human Rights and Democracy, ALSTON Philip (ed.), Human Rights Law,
Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and
Legal Theory Series, 1996, 559 p (357-383)
OST François, 1990, Jupiter, Hercule ou Hermes. Quel modèle
pour un droit post-moderne ?, Journal des Procès, n°
179, 5 octobre, p 14-20 and n° 180, 19 octobre, p 19-25
OST François, 1992a, La jurisprudence de la Cour Européenne des droits de l'homme: amorce d'un nouveau ius commune?, deWITTE Bruno, FORDER Caroline (eds.), The common law of Europe and the future of legal education - Le droit commu n de l'Europe et l'avenir de l'enseignement juridique , Deventer, Kluwer Law and Taxation Publishers, 764 p (683-720)
OST François, 1992b, Pour une théorie ludique du
droit, Droit et Société, n° 20-21, p 89-98
OST François, van de KERCHOVE Michel, 1993a, L'idée de
jeu peut-elle prétendre au titre de paradigme de la science
juridique?, Revue Interdisciplinaire d'études juridiques,
n° 30, p 191-216
OST François, 1993b, Science du Droit, ARNAUD André-Jean
(ed.), Dictionnaire encyclopédique de théorie et de sociologie
du droit, Librairie Générale de Droit et de Jurisprudence,
Cahors, 758 p (363-367)
OST François, 1996, Mémoire et Pardon, promesse et remise
en question. La déclinaison éthique des temps juridiques,
56 p, distributed during the 1996-1997 Master's course in Legal Theory at
the European Academy of Legal Theory in Brussels
OST François, 1997a, Les frontières de la juridicité
: dialectique ou autopoièse ?, ROBERT Philippe, SOUBIRAN-PAILLET
Francine, van de KERCHOVE Michel (eds.), Normes, Normes juridiques, Normes
pénales - Pour une sociologie des frontières - Tome I,
CEE, L'Harmattan, Col. Logiques Sociales, Série Déviance/GERN,
353 p (251-291)
OST François, 1997b, Towards a game theory of law, 10
p, distributed during the 1996-1997 Master's course in Legal Theory at the
European Academy of Legal Theory in Brussels
OST François, 1997c, Déployer le temps. Les conditions
de possibilité du temps social. - Synthèse, 4 p, distributed
during the 1996-1997 Master's course in Legal Theory at the European Academy
of Legal Theory in Brussels
OST François, 1997d, Déployer le temps. Les conditions
de possibilité du temps social., 48 p, distributed during the
1996-1997 Master's course in Legal Theory at the European Academy of Legal
Theory in Brussels
OST François, van de KERCHOVE Michel, 1987, Jalons pour une
théorie critique du droit, Bruxelles, Publications des Facultés
universitaires Saint-Louis, Col. Travaux et Recherches, 602 p
PANIKKAR R., 1978, The Intrareligious Dialogue, USA, Paulist Press,
104 p
PANIKKAR R., 1979, Myth, Faith and Hermeneutics - Cross-cultural
studies, USA, Paulist Press, 500 p
PANIKKAR R., 1984a, Is the notion of Human Rights a Western Concept
?, Interculture, Vol. XVII, n° 1, Cahier 82, p 28-47
PANIKKAR R., 1984b, A Dialogue on Human Rights,
Interculture, Vol. XVII, n° 2, Cahier 83, p 78-85
PANIKKAR R., 1984c, The Dialogical Dialogue, WHALING F. (ed.),
The World's Religious Traditions, Edinburgh, T. & T. Clark, 311
p (201-221)
PANIKKAR Raimon, 1993a, A Dwelling Place for Wisdom, USA, Westminster/John
Knox Press, 179 p
PANIKKAR Raimon, 1993b, The Cosmotheandric Experience - Emerging Religious
Consciousness, New York, Orbis Books, 160 p
PANIKKAR Raimon, 1995, Cultural Disarmament - The Way to Peace, USA,
Westminster John Knox Press, 142 p
PANIKKAR Raimon, 1996a, Qui a peur de perdre son identité l'a
déjà perdue, Le Monde, Mardi 2 Avril, p 13
PANIKKAR Raimon, 1996b, Un défi à la modernité
: l'esprit contemplatif, Interculture, Vol. XXIX, n° 1,
Cahier n° 130, Hiver, p 38-50
PANIKKAR Raimon, 1996c, Neuf priorités,
Interculture, Vol. XXIX, n° 1, Cahier n° 130, Hiver, p
51-62
PEERENBOOM R.P., 1993, What's Wrong with Chinese Rights? : Toward a
Theory of Rights with Chinese Characteristics, ALSTON Philip (ed.),
Human Rights Law, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library
of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 559 p (293-321)
PENNEL D.J., 1990, Approche de la Révolution
Américaine, LAPEYRE A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les
dimensions universelles des Droits de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions
spirituelles et intellectuelles des Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant,
318 p (51-79)
POPPOVIC Malak El-Chichini, PINHEIRO Paulo Sérgio, 1996,
Pauvreté, droits de l'homme et processus démocratique,
Droit et Société, n° 34, p 635-648
POSSENTI Vittorio, 1995, Human Rights and Human Nature, Persona
y Derecho - Suplemento Humana Iura de derechos humanos 5, p 195-209
REGNIER André, 1971, Mathématiser les sciences
sociales, RICHARD Philippe, JAULIN Robert (éds.), Anthropologie
et calcul, France, Union Générale d'Editions, Col. 10/18,
Série 7, 383 p (13-37)
ROBERTSON Roland, 1994, Globalization - Social Theory and Global
Culture, UK, Sage Publications, Theory, Culture & Society Series,
211 p
ROBERTSON Roland, 1996, Mapping the Global Condition : Globalization
as the Central Concept, FEATHERSTONE Mike (ed.), Global Culture
- Nationalism, Globalization and modernity, Great Britain, Sage Publications,
A Theory, Culture & Society special issue, 411 p (15-30)
ROCHER Ludo, 1978, Hindu Conceptions of Law, NANDA Ved P., SINHA
Surya Prakash (eds.), Hindu Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain,
Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series,
1996, 357 p (3-25)
ROOS Nikolas H.M., 1992, Dinosaur-Complex versus Legal Pluralism,
deWITTE Bruno, FORDER Caroline (eds.), The common law of Europe and the
future of legal education - Le droit commun de l'Europe et l'avenir de
l'enseignement juridique , Deventer, Kluwer Law and Taxation Publishers,
764 p (639-659)
ROSENBAUM Alan S., 1981, Introduction - The Editor's Perspectives on
the Philosophy of Human Rights, ROSENBAUM Alan S. (ed.), The Philosophy
of Human Rights - International Perspectives, London, Aldwych Press,
272 p (3-41)
ROULAND Norbert, 1988, Anthropologie juridique, France, PUF, Col.
Droit fondamental Droit politique et théorique, 496 p
ROULAND Norbert, 1989, Penser le droit, Droits, n°
10, p 77-79
ROULAND Norbert, 1993a, Aux confins du droit, Mayenne, Odile Jacob,
318 p
ROULAND Norbert, 1993b, La France dans l'archipel des droits de
l'Homme, Libération, 22 Mars, p 6
ROULAND Norbert, 1993c, La tradition juridique africaine et la
réception des déclarations occidentales des droits de
l'homme, Droit et Cultures, n° 26, 197-217
ROULAND Norbert, 1993d, Pluralisme juridique, ARNAUD A.J. (dir.),
Dictionnaire encyclopédique de théorie et de sociologie
du droit, Paris, LGDJ, 2e éd., p 449-450
ROULAND Norbert, 1994, Les fondements anthropologiques des droits de
l'homme, Revue générale de droit, Faculté
de droit d'Ottawa, n° 25, p 9-47
ROULAND Norbert, 1995a, Anthropological foundations of human rights,
Sélection d'articles (1989-1995), consultable au LAJP, p 1-25
ROULAND Norbert, 1995b, L'archipel des droits de l'Homme,
Sélection d'articles (1989-1995), consultable au LAJP, p
191-201
ROULAND Norbert, 1995c, La tradition juridique française et
la diversité culturelle, Sélection d'articles
(1989-1995), consultable au LAJP, p 150-169
SARDAR Ziauddin, 1993, Asian Cultures: Between Programmed and Desired
Futures, MASINI Eleonora Barbieri, ATAL Yogesh (eds.), Perspectives
on Asia's Futures III: the futures of Asian Culture (Report of UNESCO Third
Meeting on Perspectives on Asia's Futures III, Bangkok, 8-11 February
1993), Bangkok, UNESCO Principal Regional Office for Asia and the Pacific,
Social and Human Sciences in Asia and the Pacific. RUSHSAP Series of Monograph
and Occasional Papers 38, 159 p (37-56)
SEGUETTE Marie, 1993, Rationalité en questions, Bulletin de liaison du LAJP, n° 18,
p 113-118
SELZNICK Philip, 1994, The Moral Commonwealth - Social Theory and the
Promise of Community, USA, University of California Press, 550 p
SHAH Idries, 1985, Les Exploits de l'Incomparable Mulla Nasrudin,
Alençon (Orne), Le Courrier du Livre, 2e éd., 156
p
SHAH Idries, 1989, Les plaisanteries de l'incroyable Mulla Nasrudin,
Alençon (Orne), Le Courrier du Livre, 2e éd., 220
p
SHAH Idries, 1994, Apprendre à apprendre, Châtenois les
Forges, Le Courrier du Livre, Col. Soufisme vivant, 303 p
SINACEUR M.A., 1990, L'Islam et les Droits de l'Homme, LAPEYRE
A., TINGUY F. de, VASAK K. (eds.), Les dimensions universelles des Droits
de l'Homme - Volume I : Les dimensions spirituelles et intellectuelles des
Droits de l'Homme, Bruxelles, Bruylant, 318 p (149-173)
SINHA Surya Prakash, 1995a, Legal Polycentricity, PETERSEN H.,
ZAHLE H. (eds.), Legal Polycentricity : Consequences of Pluralism in
Law, UK, Dartmouth, 245 p (31-69)
SINHA Surya Prakash, 1995b, Non-Universality of Law - The Indian way
of life, NANDA Ved P., SINHA Surya Prakash (eds.), Hindu Law and
Legal Theory, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of
Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 357 p (73-77)
SOB Pierre, 1995, Le principe d'universalité des droits de l'homme
: mythe et limites, Afrique 2000, Juillet-Août-Septembre,
p 5-23
SOGYAL RINPOCHE, 1995, The tibetan book of living and dying, India,
Rupa & Co, 425 p
de SOUSA SANTOS Boaventura, 1987, Law - A Map of Misreading : Toward
a Postmodern Conception of Law, Journal of Law and Society,
n° 14, p 279-299
de SOUSA SANTOS Boaventura, 1989, Towards a Postmodern Understanding
of Law, Oñati Proceedings, n° 1, p 113-123
de SOUSA SANTOS Boaventura, 1995, Toward a New Commnon Sense - Law, Science
and Politics in the Paradigmatic Transition, New York-London, Routledge,
After the Law Series, 614 p
Statement on Human Rights, 1947, American Anthropologist,
Vol. 49, n° 4, October-December, p 539-543
SUZUKI Daisetz Teitaro, 1987, Essais sur le Bouddhisme Zen - Première
série, France, Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes,
Série Bouddhisme, 471 p
von STIETENCRON Heinrich, 1994, Menschenrechte? Sichtweisen
südasiatischer Religionen, ODERSKY Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte
: Herkunft - Geltung - Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220
p (65-89)
TABBAH Bichara, 1959, De la personne humaine à la communauté
humaine, Paris, Librairie Générale de Droit et de
Jurisprudence, 269 p
TAYLOR Charles, 1992, Atomism, AVINERI Shlomo, DE-SHALIT Avner
(eds.), Communitarianism and Individualism, USA, Oxford University
Press, Oxford Readings in Politics and Government Series, 273 p (29-50)
TAYLOR Charles, 1994, The Politics of Recognition, GUTMAN Amy
(ed.), Multiculturalism - Examining the Politics of Recognition, Princeton
(New Jersey), Princeton University Press, 175 p (25-73)
TAYLOR Charles, 1996, Sources of the Self - The Making of the Modern
Identity, Great Britain, Cambridge University Press, 601 p
TESÓN Fernanado R., 1985, International Human Rights and Cultural
Relativism, ALSTON Philip (ed.), Human Rights Law, Aldershot,
Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series,
1996, 559 p (117-146)
TODOROV Tzvetan, 1992a, Le détournement des Lumières,
Centre Georges Pompidou, Philosophie et anthropologie, Paris, Centre
Pompidou, Col. Espace international. Philosophie, 190 p (25-37)
TODOROV Tzvetan, 1992b, Nous et les autres - La réflexion
française sur la diversité humaine, Saint-Amand (Cher),
Seuil, Col. Points, Série Essais, 538 p
TOURAINE Alain, 1992 Critique de la modernité, Paris, Fayard,
2e éd., Col. Biblio Essais, 510 p
TOURAINE Alain, 1989, A travers la reconnaissance de l'Autre,
Commission nationale consultative des droits de l'homme, 1989 - Les droits
de l'homme en questions, Paris, La Documentation française, p
47-54
TROUSSON Patrick, 1995, Le recours de la science au mythe - Pour une nouvelle
rationalité, Verneuil-sur-Avre, L'Harmattan, Col. Conversciences,
277 p
TRUNGPA Chögyam, 1981, Méditation et action, Evreux, Seuil,
Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 171p
TRUNGPA Chögyam, 1979, Le mythe de la liberté et La voie de
la méditation, Mayenne, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 187
p
TRUNGPA Chögyam, 1990, Shambhala La voie sacrée du guerrier,
Isle-D'Espagnac, Seuil, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 209 p
TRUNGPA Chögyam, 1993, Le Coeur du sujet, France, Seuil, 315
p
TRUNGPA Chögyam, 1994, Mandala - Un chaos ordonné, Evreux,
Seuil, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 212 p
TRUNGPA Chögyam, 1995, Bardo - Au-delà de la folie, Evreux,
Seuil, Col. Points, Série Sagesses, 379 p
TURNBULL Colin M., 1984, The Individual, Community and Society : Rights
and Responsibilities from an Anthropological Perspective, SACK Peter,
ALECK Jonathan (eds.), Law and Anthropology, Great Britain, Dartmouth,
The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1992,
527 p (201-256)
TZITZIS Stamatios, 1995, De la theoria dikaiou à
la Théorie du Droit., Persona y Derecho, n° 32,
II, p 229-247
VACHON Robert, 1990, L'étude du pluralisme juridique - une approche
diatopique et dialogale, Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial
Law, n° 29, p 163-173
VACHON Robert, 1996, L'ère de la post-modernité - Quelques
signes et priorités - Préface, Interculture, Vol.
XXIX, n° 1, Cahier n° 130, Hiver, p 2-6
VALADIERS SJ Paul, 1994, Aktuelle Gefährdungen der
Menschenrechte, ODERSKY Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte : Herkunft
- Geltung - Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220 p (23-37)
VANDERLINDEN Jacques, 1989, Return to Legal Pluralism : Twenty Years
Later, Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, n°
28, p 149-157
VERDIER Raymond, 1983, Problématique des droits de l'homme dans
les droits traditionnels d'Afrique noire, Droit et cultures,
vol. 5, p 97-103
VERDIER Raymond, 1988, Droits des peuples et droits de l'Homme à
la lumière de l'anthropologie, Droits et cultures, vol.
15-16, p 188-190
de VITRAY-MEYEROVITCH Eva, 1995, Anthologie du Soufisme,
Saint-Amand-Montrond (Cher), Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes,
363 p
VIVEKANANDA Swâmi, 1955, Entretiens et Causeries, France, Albin
Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes, Série Hindouisme, 377
p
VIVEKANANDA Swâmi, 1970, Les Yogas pratiques (Karma, Bhakti,
Râja), Saint-Amand (Cher), Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités
vivantes, Série Hindouisme, 575 p
VIVEKANANDA Swâmi, 1972, Jnâna-Yoga, Saint-Amand (Cher),
Albin Michel, Col. Spiritualités vivantes, Série Hindouisme,
446 p
WEISS Bernard, 1978, Interpretation in Islamic Law : The Theory of
Ijtihad, EDGE Ian (ed.), Islamic Law and Legal Theory, Great
Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal
Theory Series, 1996, 608 p (273-286)
WERBLOWSKY Zwi, 1994, Menschenrechte und/oder Menschenpflichten ? Eine
jüdische Perspektive, ODERSKY Walter (ed.), Die Menschenrechte:
Herkunft - Geltung - Gefährdung; Düsseldorf, Patmos, 220 p
(38-48)
WIDMER Charles, 1992, Droits de l'Homme et Sciences de l'Homme - Pour
une éthique anthropologique , Genève, Librairie Droz S.A.,
Col. Travaux de Droit, d'Économie, de Sciences Politiques, de Sociologie
et d'Anthropologie, 234 p