DHDI
|
Christoph Eberhard 30/04/97
There are people who
strive to invent lenses that will provide a comprehensive world view; there
are others who prefer to look through their glasses in order to find out
what is going on in the world. (ROTTLEUTHNER 1989b : 780). In the following
pages we will try not to much to philosophize about what efficacy
of a whole legal order could mean in contrast to the efficacy of a a single
law. We will rather try to look at the issue through sociological glasses
oriented towards the search for possible empirical criteria allowing us to
define efficacy of a whole legal order. In order to do so we
will start by defining what is meant by the efficacy of a single law and
by exposing how such efficacy can be empirically determined and the problems
that are linked to it (1). We then will deal with the conceptual and
practical problems linked to the transposition of the concept from the realm
of a single law to the realm of a whole legal order (2).
Finally, in order to give some hints of what efficacy of a whole legal order
could mean without getting lost in philosophical abstractions we will try
to draw on the lessons we could learn from the efficacy of the
imported legal (state) orders in african states (3).
(1) First
of all let us define what efficacy means, especially in contrast with
effectivity. By effectivity it is the degree of realisation in
social practices, of rules enunciated by law, which is designated, whereas
with efficacy we refer to the appreciation of the consequences
of legal norms and of their adequacy to the goals they are intended to achieve
(Effectivité : 217; Efficacité : 219).
Rottleuthner makes a further distinction between two possible ways of
understanding efficacy (Wirksamkeit). For him
efficacy can be either understood as the evaluation of the goal
attainment by the law or as the establishment of the causal link between
changed behaviour and the fact that this behaviour has been actually changed
by the effect of the law and not by some other factors (ROTTLEUTHNER 1987
: 55). To show in an empirical verifiable manner how and why legal norms
operate and turn out to be or not to be efficacious, Rottleuthner uses a
model first developed by K.D. Opp and which has been refined by A. Diekman
(ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 56-57 - I will use the english version of the model
distributed during the lectures in the following pages). In this model there
are two kinds of variables influencing the degree of compliance with a law.
The variables of a first degree directly influence the degree of compliance
with a law whereas the variables of a second degree only have an indirect
influence mediated through the variables of the first degree. Examples of
variables of the first degree are the degree of expected positive or negative
sanctions in cases of compliance or non-compliance with a law, the degree
of information about a law, the frequency of the type of situation to which
the law might apply. Examples of variables of the second degree are the rate
of detection, the degree of social stigmatization of a violation, the perceived
moral competence of the legislator, the dissemination of information by the
mass media (to see the corelations between those variables it is useful to
have a look at the model : ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 57). To complete this first
model Rottleuthner proposes a second one which enables him to handle laws
which do not work with permissions and prohibitions (Gebote und
Verbote) but which use financial incentives or compensations or which
provide procedural offers (Verfahrensangebote) which can be used
or not (ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 62). Here it is not the degree of compliance
with a law which is relevant but the degree of use (Inanspruchname)
of the law. What changes mainly in contrast to the first model is that being
informed presupposes, more than just mere knowledge of the law, a more detailed
knowledge of the procedures it proposes. Furthermore the problem arises that
there may be people behaving in conformity with the law to get the financial
incentives, but who would have behaved the same way without the law - in
which case there is no direct causal relation between the law and the behaviour,
and thus no efficacy of the law in Rottleuthner's second sense (ROTTLEUTHNER
1987 : 63-64). Problems arise from these two models in checking the efficacy
of a law. First the issue of efficacy is seen from the point of view of a
dyadic relation between norm-sender and norm-receiver, between order and
obedience, between offer and acceptance of the offer. Thus the norm-receiver
is perceived as a lonely individual, abstracted of all his social relationships
and the models do not take into account the roles that pressure groups or
not directly adressed groups (ex : not the norm-receivers but the ones whom
the norm should protect) play in the compliance with the law and thus in
the realisation of the goal of the legislator (ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 71).
Furthermore this individual is seen as fundamentally rational, leading thus
rather to an analysis in terms of Zweck- rather than
Wertrationalität (ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 73-74). Last but not
least the goal of the legislator is often far from being clear, which makes
it difficult to check if the laws he passes manage to achieve their goal
(ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 74-75). There is also one more general problem of efficacy
research - its aim is to check in an empirical way the direct causality between
laws and their effects and the conformity of that effects to the aim of the
law. It thus tries to demonstrate simple causalities in the eminent complex
field that society is and thus does not have the possibility to establish
the ideal conditions for scientific experimentations and has to be content
with quasi-experiments (Quasi-Experimente) which are comparative
researches either in space (compare the effect of a same action on different
groups (Vergleichsgruppen-Untersuchungen) : ex: the abolition
of death penalty in different countries) or in time
(Zeitreiheanalysen) (ROTTLEUTHNER 1987 : 75-76).
There are thus problems in
Rotleuthner's efficacy research. Nevertheless this approach may be the only
one trying to deal empirically with the problem of efficacy instead of
transposing the whole problem on an intellectual debate where the whole empirical
problem may be lost. This problem of efficacy becoming a problem purely internal
to the operation of a legal system itself seems to arise in Luhmann's
autopoietic theory of law. In this theory the scope of
interest (...) moves from input-output relationships, from exchanges between
system and environment, to the internal operations of the systems
themselves. and the theoretical perspective moves away from design
and control to autonomy, from planning to evolution. (ROTTLEUTHNER
1989b : 781-782). Thus while turning now to the question of efficacy of a
whole legal order we will try to keep in mind our commitment to empirical
research and to the theoretical perspective in which the legal
order has effects on society, which can be measured, even if
not with very high precision, and even though it may be difficult.
(2) The
first question we have to ask ourselves is how we are going to define the
legal order in such a way that it will permit us to undertake
empirical research on its efficacy. Rottleuthner notices that l'objet
des recherches de la sociologie du droit n'est pas le droit comme un complexe
de faits (...), mais les faits en relation au droit, c'est-à-dire
les faits qui présentent une référence aux normes
légales. (ROTTLEUTHNER 1992 : 81). As concerns the norms themselves
Rottleuthner argues that sociologists do not have, like anthropologists,
to determine what these norms actually are but can rely on their correct
procedural creation by the legal system to consider them as law. Their job
is rather to confront the law and its effects, law in the books
and law in action, rather than to try to define what law is.
They thus have a state (étatiste) view of law (ROTTLEUTHNER
1992 : 77-78). For our efficacy research of a whole legal order we will thus
consider the legal order as the set of rules and institutions steming from
the state in order to organize it (and thus to organize the society that
makes up the state).We will thus already consider as a legal order a set
of state rules and institutions which is formally and professionally
institutionalised (professionally because otherwise we could not study the
application and the effects of the legal order as it would just remain an
abstract idea) but will not take into account its sociological
institutionalisation (VAN HOECKE 1996 : 19ss). Indeed the 'sociological
institutionalisation' of the law refers to the acceptance of the legal system
by the people to whom it is meant to apply. From the point of view of the
legal system it is the efficacy of the law which is in question. (VAN
HOECKE 1996 : 22). So not only are we not going not to take it into account
to avoid having some circular definitions of legal order and
efficacy, but furthermore will this sociological
institutionalisation be one of the facts related to law that we will
study to determine the efficacy of the legal order. Having said all this,
and aware that we are treating the legal order as something distinct from
the rest of society but which nevertheless influences it, we now can start
thinking about the efficacy of such a legal order.
The problem of efficacy being
linked to the attainment of specific goals through laws we will not dwell
on the problems of the conformity of the legal staff, which relate rather
to the effectivity of the legal order and are a precondition to its efficacy.
The question of the efficacy of the legal order can thus be summed up in
the question if the state succeeds through its institutions and
through the rules it edicts to achieve the goals it has set to itself. We
find here the same problems as already encountered above - at first sight
they may even see to be increased as we are no more dealing with a simple
law adressed to a specific group of people and having a more or less specific
object but with a whole meaby very heterogenous and complex legal order with
influences on an as much heterogenous and complex society. Doing efficacy
research here in terms of research of individual behaviour according to all
the different rules and institutions that affect the different individuals
seems completely impossible, especially if we place ourselves in a perspective
on the legal order which is proposed by Rottleuthner and which advocates
the taking into account of various dimensions of law, of a
gradual concept of law, of a variety of types of
statutes and which invites us to use the multitude of definitions
of law's function in empirical research in order to find out to what extent
they are achieved by taking for example not only into account the system's
but also the actor's point of view (ROTLEUTHNER 1989b : 794-795). Thus the
option of empirical research seems to close down and we have decided not
to follow internalizing system approaches à la Luhmann
which tend to shift the problematic of empirical efficacy away from empiric
evidence to system's theory which may lead to wrong pictures of relity by
for example constructing regulatory crisises where there may
be none (ROTTLEUTHNER 1989a : 273 ss). How then research about the efficacy
of a whole legal order ? How find out, otherwise than by philosophical
speculations, what the aim of a legal order is, and to what extent it succeeds
in realizing this aim ? I think here the quasi-experiment made possible by
the exportation of european (state) legal orders into non european environments
(the former colonies which now provide us with comparative groups playing
the role of a mirroir déformant) may give some insights
into what the aims of our legal orders may be and to what extent they may
succeed in realizing them. As Alliot says concerning the study of african
societies : Dans le miroir noir, nous apercevons la face cachée
de l'Occident. (ALLIOT 1980 : 155)
(3)
Unfortunately we will not have enough space here to really develop our insights.
But we will nevertheless try to open the path for some reflections. The state
legal order has been used in african countries after the independances in
a very openly aim persuing manner. This can be seen very well in the
constitutions of the african states (the Grundnorm of their legal
order) which have a marked ideological caracter and have to be understood
more as a charta, a programme of (political, economic, social ...) action
rather than as the basis and the guarantee of a legal order in the sense
of a set of rules and institutions trying to organise the rule of
law. As Conac says : Les constitutions, en Afrique, ont une foncion
pédagogique. Elles doivent contribuer à la formation politique
et à la mobilisation des masses et des élites. C'est pourquoi
certaines dispositions constitutionnelles énoncent des principes
d'organisation sociale, fixent à la nation des objectifs à
atteindre, définissent à l'intention des gouvernants des programmes
d'action, correspondent à de véritables choix de
société : elles font de l'Etat le garant d'une philosophie
politique ou le promoteur d'une idéologie de développement.
(CONAC 1980b : 387). A western lawyer would be puzzled and meaby even shocked
by the explicitely value ladden constitutions and their very flexible use
by the leaders of the african states according to the needs of the moment.
More over will he be shocked by the explicit political use of law which raises
questions as to the relation between droit du pouvoir and
pouvoir du droit. The african experience has shown that the capacity
to use law, a whole legal order, as a tool for social change, national
unification, economic development, has been highly overevaluated (CONAC 1980a
: XVI). A legal order thus seems unefficaceous to bring about social changes
if itself and its goals are not shared by society as a whole and do not stem
from it. The inefficacy of the legal order becomes apparent in the lack of
respect of the installed order by the legal staff itself as well as by the
political order. It is also characterized by the lack of penetration of the
legal order into society. The state order is to large extents either ignored
or domesticated by the citizens who either rely on their traditional law
or build up their own droit de la pratique founded on popular
legitimacy and which can even come to be implicitely or explicitely recognised
by the state which suspends then the application of its own law (LE ROY 1991
: 118-119). Thus it seems that while speaking of the efficacy of a whole
legal order one cannot stay at a superficial level, noticing a regulatory
crisis of the law and concluding from it a lack of efficacy of the legal
order. One could at the most conclude to the inefficacy of a part of the
legal order (ex: trade law - and even such a category seems to broad) but
one cannot draw any conclusions as to the efficacy of the underlying paradigm
which is the whole legal order and in which some disfunctions may take place
without challenging the efficacy of the legal order as a whole which still
remains the accepted structuring principle of life in society. The problem
of the efficacy of a whole legal order thus seems to need to be posed on
a much more fundamental level which comparative research on the efficacy
of legal orders in different cultures seems to be able, at least partly,
to reveal. It has to be posed on the very level of the acceptance of the
structural paradigm that it constitutes. A legal order can only be considered
as efficaceous if it fits the expectations of the society it wants to order
and thus can be said to really structure the life of a society (on law as
structure of society see : LUHMANN 1985 : 103 ss) by providing a generally
accepted framework to the action of the people (individually or in groups)
to whom the legal order is meant to apply. This general acceptance of a legal
order can be empirically checked by research on the behaviour (rejection,
use, creation or drawing back on alternative modes of organizing social
interactions) of the different actors to whom it is supposed to apply (citizens,
legal staff, political power ...). The comparative quasi-experiment of the
reception of the state legal order in different cultural areas may provide
criteria to work out a model of evaluation of the efficacy of a whole legal
order. This model can (must ?!) of course be a gradual model ranging from
complete efficacy, through greater or lower partial efficacy (efficaceous
on some points, to provide a structure for some social interactions and for
some social actors, but not providing such a structure for others) to complete
inefficacy. This research could be supported by anthropological research
which show us the links existing between Penser Dieu (et) Penser le
Droit (Alliot quoted in ROULAND 1988 : 401), Dieu standing
here for the ultimate structural principle on which societies rely upon to
conceive about the universe and which influences the way they will structure
their life in this universe, and thus in their society. In our western societies
this structural principle is the one of an exterior god who imposes his order
on his creation through general laws who have to be observed by all his creatures
equally, even though the figure of God has been replaced by modernity
by the figure of the State (ROULAND 1988 : 404-405). In our view
the role of the legal order is seen as to constitute a neutral and secure
frame for an ordered living together which is achieved through the means
of general and impersonal rules, in other words it is to establish the
rule of law, the Rechtsstaat, or the Etat de
Droit. It seems to me that in these terms, which in the light of what
we have seen above especially concerning the taking into account of non-western
experiences, are not to broad and not so evident when one tries to think
about the efficacy of a whole legal order, our western legal orders still
seem very efficacious. The analysis in terms of regulatory crisis
should thus in my view not be extended to test the general efficacy of a
whole legal order but should remain limited to specific areas of law where
efficacy research as developed in (1) can be used to empirically check
this hypothesis. It is only in this way and by investigating upon the efficacy
of whole legal orders by comparative researh in different cultures not sharing
the same basic presuppositions as to their worldview as us, but having imported
western legal orders to organise their societies, that we will be able to
develop some meaningful and empirically grounded research on what the efficacy
of a whole legal order could mean in contrast to the efficacy of a single
law. As Michel Alliot writes :
ALLIOT Michel, 1980, Le miroir noir - Images
réfléchies de l'Etat et du droit français,
1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions à des colloques, textes
du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris, LAJP, 1989 p 169-187
ALLIOT Michel, 1983, L'anthropologie juridique
et le droit des manuels, 1953-1989 Recueil d'articles, contributions
à des colloques, textes du Recteur Michel Alliot , Paris,
LAJP, p 251-268
CONAC Gérard, 1980a, La vie du droit
en Afrique, CONAC Gérard (éd.), Dynamiques et
finalités des droits africains - Actes du colloque de la Sorbonne
La vie du Droit en Afrique, Paris, Economica, Col. Recherches
Panthéon-Sorbonne Université de Paris I, Série: Sciences
juridiques, 509 p (V-XXXX)
CONAC Gérard, 1980b, Les constitutions
des états d'Afrique et leur effectivité, CONAC Gérard
(éd.), Dynamiques et finalités des droits africains - Actes
du colloque de la Sorbonne La vie du Droit en Afrique, Paris,
Economica, Col. Recherches Panthéon-Sorbonne Université de
Paris I, Série: Sciences juridiques, 509 p (385-413)
Effectivité, ARNAUD André-Jean
(ed.), Dictionnaire encyclopédique de théorie et de sociologie
du droit, Librairie Générale de Droit et de Jurisprudence,
Cahors, 1993, 758 p (217-219)
Efficacité, ARNAUD André-Jean
(ed.), Dictionnaire encyclopédique de théorie et de sociologie
du droit, Librairie Générale de Droit et de Jurisprudence,
Cahors, 1993, 758 p (219-221)
LE ROY Etienne, 1991, Les usages politiques
du droit, COULON Christian, MARTIN Denis-Constant (éds.), Les
afriques politiques, Saint-Amand (Cher), La Découverte, Col. Textes
à l'appui, Série Histoire contemporaine, 294 p (109-122)
LUHMANN Niklas, 1985, A sociological theory
of law, London, Boston, Melbourne and Henley, Routledge & Kegan Paul,
International Library of Sociology, 421 p
LUHMANN Niklas, 1988, The Unity of the Legal
System, TEUBNER Günther (ed.), Autopoietic Law : A New Approach
to Law and Society, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin - New York, p 12-35
ROTTLEUTHNER Hubert, 1987, Einführung in
die Rechtssoziologie, Germany, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft Darmstadt,
200 p
ROTTLEUTHNER Hubert, 1989a, The limits of
Law - The Myth of a Regulatory Crisis, International Journal of
the Sociology of Law, n°17, p 273-285
ROTTLEUTHNER Hubert, 1989b, A Purified Sociology
of Law : Niklas Luhman on the Autonomy of the Legal System, Law
& Society Review, Vol. 23, n°5, p 779-797
ROTTLEUTHNER Hubert, 1992, Le concept
sociologique de droit, Revue interdisciplinaire d'études
juridiques, n°29, p 67-84
ROULAND Norbert, 1988, Anthropologie
juridique, France, PUF, Col. Droit fondamental Droit politique et
théorique, 496 p
TEUBNER Günther, 1992, Regulatory Law
: Chronicle of a Death Foretold, Social & Legal Studies,
Vol. 1, p 451-475
VAN HOECKE, 1996, Jurisprudence, Reader
for the academic year 1996-1997 at the European Academy of Legal Theory,
141 p