20/06/2004

 

 

 

 

Beyond Legal Pluralism

A Dynamic and Intercultural Approach to Law in India

 

Christoph Eberhard

 

Faculs universitaires Saint Louis, Bruxelles

Laboratoire dAnthropologie Juridique de Paris

 

(first draft of a paper published in

 Indian Socio-Legal Journal XXXI, 2005, p 131-148)

 

No purely theoretical solution can ever be adequate to the problem of pluralism ; and this almost by definition. A problem which has a theoretical answer is not a pluralistic problem. () Pluralism begins when the praxis compels us to take a stance in the effective presence of the other, when the praxis makes it impossible to avoid mutual interference, and the conflict cannot be solved by the victory of one part or party. () The problem of pluralism arises only when we feel we suffer the incompatibility of differing worldviews and are at the same time forced by the praxis of our factual coexistence to seek survival.[1]

 

This whole publication illustrates this insight : pluralism is before all linked to praxis. It is not merely an intellectual problem. It may thus seem surprising that in our conclusion we propose to go beyond legal pluralism and thus to engage in some kind of intellectual play. Have we not underlined the usefulness of legal pluralism in our introduction, highlighting that At this stage of the growth and acceptance of the concept of legal pluralism, an aspiration can be expressed that increasing awareness of its utility will ultimately serve the purpose of enriching our general understanding of law and of the relationship between law and society in all legal systems, having a colonial past or not  (p 5) ? What could be the use to challenge, an approach in terms of legal pluralism, which indeed serves the purpose to raise the awareness of the legal community (scholars and practitioners) to the complexities of the law and society relationships ? And to point thus to our praxis in trying to understand and put into perspective Law in action ?

 

Let us be clear right from the start. As the subtitle of this contribution suggests, we want to emphasize the need to focus increasingly on the challenges of dynamic and intercultural approaches to Law[2], which could then also lead to what we would term a genuinely pluralist approach to Law, and which could maybe also contribute to a better understanding of situations of legal pluralism. The point is thus not so much to disqualify approaches in terms of legal pluralism and to challenge them. It rather consists in complementing them with a different perspective which is still dealing with the core question of pluralism, but whose aim it is, rather than putting the stress on a recognition and a description of an existing legal pluralism, to draw the epistemological, and maybe even existential, implications of the recognition of this legal pluralism. Is it not that what we construct as situations of legal pluralism points to the underlying necessity to open up towards a more plural view of social reality and of Law ? Maybe this new shift of perspective will permit to shed some light on what appears as some of the blind spots of the present work. It may thus also open up paths for possible future researches. The endeavor seems all the more interesting as classical conceptions of Indian Law seem to have been fundamentally pluralist. Thus in the Indian context, an approach which may appear as very new or even revolutionary to a modern lawyer, may in fact reveal a continuity with preexisting understandings of Law, although the classical Indian legal pluralism is obviously different from the present situation. The discussion of a pluralist approach to Law from an Indian perspective may thus also permit not only to highlight the challenges of legal pluralism in India, but also to underline the contributions of the Indian tradition in the intercultural dialogue on Law or the constitution of more intercultural theories of Law.

 

It seems to me, that many contributions to this publication although explicitely dealing with legal pluralism, do in fact also, at least implicitely, deal with a pluralist approach to Law, as I will expose it in this article. As Ajit Menon points out in the first contribution to this volume (p 4)  customary law is not necessarily a well articulated phenomena with clearly defined rules of use (as opposed to rules in use) and procedures for monitoring and enforcing these rules. A more open-ended approach to customary law traversing time is used despite the fact that it might erase the distinction between law and other forms of normative ordering. In terms of method, this customary law (in the absence perhaps of clearly defined rules of use) can be disentangled by undertaking a study of land use practices (rules in use). Examining everyday agrarian practices, the cultivation of land, the grazing of cattle and the collection of forest produce will help understand how resources are allocated and for what purposes. These practices constitute the legal domain though there are few signs of rules or an authority enforcing it.  This shift of perspective where we try to understand Law as legal phenomena from the point of view of the whole social reality and which thus seems to be more concerned with a recognition and an understanding of the plural nature of the legal domain rather than of the coexistence of legal orders seems to be present throughout this publication. It is closely linked to the need expressed in many papers to do justice to the dynamic and intercultural aspects of legal reality, of which state law or modern law constitutes but the tip of the iceberg. It is true, as Satyapriya Rout (p 4) points out that  One of the important characteristics of legal pluralism is that instead of viewing law as a static phenomenon, it conceptualises law as a dynamic force, which can be modified and negotiated to suit into situations concerned. .  Thus a dynamic approach to Law is in no way a novelty of what I will call a pluralist approach to Law it just constitutes an explicit shift of perspective which remains implicit in many writings and which is well illustrated in this quotation : while we start to pluralize our view of law by recognizing legal pluralism, we are then led to give a new meaning to Law, a more plural, dynamic and complex meaning. And also a meaning which will have to take into account what cultures who do not necessarily think in terms of  law  have to say about the reviewed definition of the  legal field , thus leading us even further in our pluralization of legal pluralism. As Amarpal Singh noted in his article (p 4) With this broad understanding of legal pluralism, when we turn to the Indian paradigm, the scene is peculiarly pluralist, though glossed over by the common law system of  English origin . But this endeavour towards a pluralization, and interculturalization, of our theories should not be understood as a postmodern deconstructive endeavour. If deconstruction is a necessary moment of our reflexion, the real challenge seems to lie in the proposal of renewed theories of Law which build on an additive logic, meaning a logic that tries to do justice to all the encountered phenomena without reducing their originlaity in an undue manner. It is such a deconstructive / reconstructive approach that I will try to expose in the following pages.

As a starting point, I will discuss some elements presented during the XIIIth congress of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism held in Chiang Mai in 2002 on the limits and contradictions of analyses in terms of legal pluralism, or more generally of anthropological approaches to Law which I will put in dialogue with recent approaches to pluralist approaches to Law, especially from the Laboratoire dAnthropologie Juridique de Paris (LAJP)[3] and the Intercultural Institute of Montral (IIM)[4]. This choice may seem arbitrary, but despite the inherent interest of the material presented at this conference, we must acknowledge that the latter constitutes the starting point of the present dynamics. It thus seems useful to go back to the roots, in order to take the reflexions further and thus try to inscribe our endeavour into a cumulative logic. I will then move to a presentation of how questions of Law and of pluralism can be put from an Indian perspective. This will permit to interculturalize our frame of understanding and to open up doors for genuine intercultural dialogue and will lead to the proposal of a shift from analyses in terms of legal pluralism to the challenge of an intercultural and dynamic pluralist approach to Law. The latter is especially anchored in the approaches of the Laboratoire dAnthropologie Juridique de Paris and of the Intercultural Institute of Montral. The presentation will thus also serve the purpose to continue to familiarize an Anglophone audience with Francophone approaches to the anthropology of Law[5].

 

What are the stakes and the limits of legal pluralism ?

 

The main insights we would like to discuss here are those presented by Franz von Benda-Beckmans review article on the state of the art in the field Whos afraid of legal pluralism ?[6]. The fundamental question for Franz von Benda-Beckman is that of the definition of law[7] for the purpose of its anthropological study. He introduces his reflexion with a clarification of what one can understand and of what one should expect from analytical concepts. () in most societies, and probably in all contemporary societies, there is a great complexity of cognitive and normative conceptions that constitute forms of legitimate social, economic and political power and organization ; provide standards for permissible action and for the validity of transactions, as well as ideas and procedures for dealing with problematic situations, notably the management of conflict and disputes. () While social and legal scientists perceptions of such complexity and its implications for further conceptual, methodological and theoretical ideas vary significantly, we do not have to prove to anyone that it is there. The question is : How do we get to grips with the complexity ? With which categories and concepts can we make sense of it, conceptually and theoretically ?[8]. It appears clearly that legal pluralism is nothing more than a useful concept in order to try to get to grips with the complexity of social reality when looked upon from the point of view of its normative characters. It is also not an all-encompassing concept and does not seek to be the ultimate and complete explanation of the law and society relationship. As Franz von Benda-Beckman notes, The concepts of law or legal pluralism are only a part of our wider conceptual and analytical tools.[9] We could add that there may be cases in our research where we may want to avoid these terms. Indeed the critical argument that terming phenomena which are non-state law, law, or to talk about law in societies which do not have translations of this word as they share in another worldvision, should be taken seriously. If indeed, we place ourselves on the stage of ethnography or even ethnology[10], we may prefer to avoid to impose foreign concepts on the functioning of a society, and we may prefer to render the ordering of this society through indigenous terms and their explanation. But if we want to move towards the general comparison of human experiences, we will have to construct a frame of comparison. It is clear that other societies may not have chosen the same kind of frames, and that every comparison is rooted somewhere there can be no non-located comparison. And this location is not only linked to the worldvision in which the person comparing is rooted but also to his aim, to the perspective he is taking in order to understand a particular thing[11]. But, does this mean that we are irremediably drawn into an all dissoluting intersubjectivity where nothing can ultimately be known ? Definitely not. If we do recognize the inherent limits of our endeavor it does very much make sense to ask how different societies do put the questions and answers to what we approach as law in our societies and this may lead us to have to revise our taken for granted assumptions about what law is, and may lead us to review our analytical concept of law, which it seems, will necessarily have to be pluralized in order to be able to come to grips with the observed reality - as its modern understanding is essentially uniformizing.

 

It should be noted that on a level, not foreseen by Claude Lvi-Strauss, it could again become necessary to leave the frame of law or of legal pluralism. Indeed legal anthropology, and anthropology in general will always partly remain an opening up of the western scientific window towards other cultures which can permit us to get more adequate knowledge on human beings from a Western point of view. But it cannot be ignored that cultures with different worldviews have developed different epistemologies, and different ways of understanding and organizing their lives. And one should take seriously the aim of these cultures to also propose general theories on how we live together. Today it does not seem sufficient to only open up the Western window. It must also be recognized that there are diverse windows, and that all these windows cannot be reduced or integrated into one unique window. There thus emerges a need for intercultural dialogue, to which we will return in the next section.

 

But let us now come back to Franz von Benda-Beckmanns analysis. The four main epistemological issues he raises are 1) which criteria permit to identify something as being legal ? 2) How do we deal with difference, meaning how do we indicate the sets of criteria in which these phenomena vary ? 3) What type of legal complexity can be termed legal pluralism ? Does legal pluralism require the existence of more than one legal system or order, or are legal mechanisms sufficient, and can one speak of legal pluralism within one legal order?[12] 4) And perhaps the most important yet least discussed question : what does existence or co-existence mean ?[13]

 

We can see that the questions on legal pluralism automatically lead us to a reflexion on law and on its definition. We can note that comparative lawyers also start to get more and more aware of the need to link their comparison to an explicit legal theory : indeed how could we compare something if we do not know what ?[14]

 

Let us see what insights Franz von Benda-Beckmann proposes. He starts by giving a general definition of what he calls law. He then deals with the empirical variations of this cover term and finally puts the question of the relationship between law and the state.

 

For Franz von Benda-Beckmann legal phenomena are objectified cognitive and normative conceptions, qualified by a number of specific criteria () Law is a dimension of social organization consisting of cognitive and normative conceptions for which validity for a certain category of people or territory is asserted. These conceptions recognize and restrict societys members autonomy to behave and construct their own conceptions. Through legal conceptions situation images of elements of the social and natural world (persons, organizations, natural resources, social relationships, behaviour, occurrences) are constructed, evaluated and given relevance. Relevance means that definite consequences are attached to and rationalized by reference to the legal categories of relevance : a) permissibility, b) validity, and c) simple relevance. Law becomes manifest in two major manifestations, a) as general rules and and principles that evaluate typified situation images for typified consequences as conditional if-then schemes, and b) as concrete law that evaluates concrete situation images for concrete consequences in terms of as-therefore rationalization.[15] This being said the question which arises is the one of the actual shape these phenomena take in human societies. Franz von Benda-Beckmann thus turns to the question of legal variations. For our purpouse, we will directly turn to his thoughts on the variation in the existences of law which he presents after the morphological and as part of the functional variations[16], and more especially to the question of what happens to law in plural contexts. It is in these contexts that the self-evident representations of what law is, get challenged as there exist different competing laws. () processes of the reproduction of law usually are more explicit under conditions of legal pluralism, when people are aware of alternative normative repertoires and/or procedures in which these can be used. Of course also in the context of legal pluralism, different participants and decision-makers may refer to the same law. But they often mobilize different legal repertoires against each other (folk law against state law, religious law against folk or state law etc.). They may also accumulate elements of different systems or compound them to create hybrid forms. But generally the condition of legal pluralism challenges the exclusiveness and self-evidence of any single normative system. One is no longer concerned with the question of wether or not to reproduce elements of the law as against non-legal modes. Choices between legal systems are thinkable. Orientation at and invocation of one of the alternatives therefore require an explicit justification. Reference to the rules of one system () then often get the character of a political and ideological statement. One not only opts for a limited number of rules that should apply to a problematic situation, but for the whole sub)system of which these rules form part. And through this reproduction of one subsystem in view of alternatives, also the relationship between the subsystems is reproduced.[17]

 

Although favouring an analytical concept of law which unlinks the relationship between law and the state, it appears that an underlying assumption of his approach seems to be a coexistence of legal systems understood as normative systems. What seems to be understood by a normative system is a set of norms which can be clearly identified and which would apply if the specific system is chosen for conflict resolution. This implicitely refers to the state-law model a continental European lawyer may spontaneously have in mind : a collection of general and impersonal norms which preexist a conflict, which are linked together in a systemic way and which only need to be applied in order to solve conflicts or to put into forms peaceful social reproduction. Choice of one legal rule entails the choice of the whole system or subsystem as Franz von Benda-Beckmann writes. Also in a broader understanding of law as he has exposed above, not only legal systems as understood from a strictly positivist lawyers perspective are taken into account. It is interesting to underline his statement One is no longer concerned with the question of wether or not to reproduce elements of the law as against non-legal modes. Choices between legal systems are thinkable.[18] There is an interesting shift in these two sentences, where it seems that in situations of legal pluralism non-legal modes suddenly turn into legal systems. We find this shift very interesting and feel that it synthesizes very well the whole challenge of the opening up of our concept of law once we try to understand the legal game in a plural setting and in all its complexity. Nevertheless, although turning the non-legal which displays legal characteristics for the legal anthropologist into a legal system permits to seriously take into account these realities without disqualifying them a priori from the analysis, it remains that the way it is done seems to mould it into a very state law informed form. And in my mind, the fact to also open up the analysis to subsystems or even to an analysis of clusters of law does not change this predicament very much[19]. Although an analysis in terms of the contexts of law and of legal clusters seems to enter into a more dynamic and processual, and also more blurred approach to the legal game than a classical systemic approach, it is clear that it remains within a systemic analysis. Indeed for Keebet von Benda-Beckmann () the definition of a problem invokes different sets of legal concepts, norms, procedures, and institutions () It is implicitely assumed that the contexts in which problems are defined are fairly clear, if not for the researcher, then at least for the actors involved. This is not always the case : legal contexts may be clear, but they are often diffuse, contested, and they change over time. Moreover it is not always clear what the precise scope of relevant norms is in a particular context. This paper explores how legal contexts are shaped, used and changed. I shall argue that understanding legal contexts requires insight of the systemic character of legal systems.[20] For the moment let us content ourselves with a critique Monique Nuitjen has presented to this kind of approach during the Chiang Mai conference in her presentation of a force fields approach in legal anthropology : () the limitation of these perspectives, in my view, is the belief that systems of norms form the basis of social order. Even though they recognize that rules can be manipulated, they still believe in norms as the basis of social order. However, in my view, orders are not necessarily rule or norm-based. They are based on many different elements of which rules wether state rules or customary rules only form a certain part. In my view, the search for normative orders can give a distorted and too schematic view of socio-political life. Furthermore, too little attention is paid to the fact that struggle and power relations are central components of the patterning process.[21] This critique could maybe also be applied to Gordon Woodmans approach, who, although questioning the possibility of legal systems in an approach of legal pluralism[22] still proposes to analyze situations from the point of a view of the application of multiple laws in a given context to given actors, with reference to Jacques Vanderlindens revised concept of legal pluralism[23].

 

It is important to note that the different perspectives on legal pluralism or on legal phenomena may not be mutually exclusive and are often informed by the diverse field experiences or areas of interest of different legal anthropologists[24]. The following developments advocating a shift from legal pluralism to a pluralist approach to Law should thus be seen as complementary to the developments exposed until now. If we consider that they have a wider scope, they seem especially relevant for the Indian context, whose whole underlying worldview is fundamentally pluralist.

 

 

An Approach to Pluralism and to Law in India

 

It may seem strange to be pointing out some specificities of the Indian worldview with regards to Law in the conclusion of a whole issue of the Indian Socio-Legal Journal especially dedicated to legal pluralism in India. Is that not with what we should have started ? Or is it even necessary as the whole work has been carried out in an Indian context ? And am I, a foreigner really the most competent person for doing this ? Or is the purpose not before all to enter into a potentially fruitful dialogue between Western and Indian concepts of pluralism, thus pluralizing our approaches to pluralism which would not be truly pluralistic if we could in the end reduce them to a new kind of unity ?[25]

 

My aim here will be to show, to what extent it seems that imposing a vision of legal pluralism on the Indian legal reality, may be a way of missing Indias original relationship to pluralism and to Law, which can in my eyes better be captured in the view of a pluralist approach to Law. What I will thus try to do here is an intercultural opening up of the question of legal pluralism via an Indian perspective. This opening up will then lead to propose in the next section a model or rather a method to approach Law in a plural way which can complement the former approaches in terms of legal pluralism.

 

In the vision of legal pluralism exposed above we can notice a few underlying assumptions : 1) Law is seen as general and impersonal norms, which can be identified and abstracted from other domains of life. The approach is thus an idealistic approach. These norms also have a tendency to appear in an organized form, as legal systems, and thus have a systemic and rational character. 2) Law or the legal system is seen as something external which imposes itself onto people and situations. One has to submit to these laws or legal systems in order to uphold order. The law or the legal system is thus superior to those it is supposed to regulate. 3) Law or a legal system aim for exclusivity : they claim the monopoly of ordering, controlling social reproduction and conflict resolution. This exclusivity is linked to their external and superior character : there is no place for a concurrent legitimate ordering which would stem from either groups on a lower level within the system or from individuals. 4) Although this is not clearly apparent in the presentation above, it stems from the inscription of analyses of legal pluralism in the frame of Western social sciences, that the analysis centers on social phenomena, e.g. relationships between human beings living together in societies. The approach is thus mainly anthropocentred and does not take into account cosmic or divine realities. Legitimacy of law is thus most of all seen as legitimacy of human made institutions and their implementation, which puts focus on the relationship between law and power (politics). Transcendental or non-human rules are not sources of law or only become so if they are written down and put into legal form by humans. The approach is also rather based on an analysis in terms of rights than in terms of duties. 5) Legal pluralism arises or exists because in actual life there is conflict or at least coexistence of different norms or normative orders which may be in competition for legitimacy. It is a pluralism of basically monolithical entitities (laws or legal systems) which overlap, clash, partially intermingle, avoid each other etc.

 

Let us now have a look at a classical Indian outlook on Law, centered around the idea of dharma, and contrast it with this view. In order to do so we will have a look at classical Hindu Law. In doing so I do not wish to reduce Indian reality to Hindu reality, especially if we keep in mind that Hinduism is also a concept with monolithic tendencies and which has been imposed from outside on a basically pluralist reality[26]. I also do not intend to say that modern legal reality should again be attuned to classical Indian Law and that a golden age has to be recovered. Times have changed and many articles of this issue of Indian Socio-Legal Journal have highlighted the complexities of contemporary legal realities between more traditional and more modern, or even postmodern thrusts, and between diverse dynamics and logics on more or less global or local scales and on more long or short term periods. But many articles of this issue have also highlighted the fact that traditional conceptions of Law do continue to inform the way that Law in India is thought of and practiced as well by the state and its officials as by the citizens. So while dealing with classical Hindu law, what seems important to us is to highlight an attitude towards Law which actually has informed the way the law from colonizing powers was received on the subcontinent and which continues to inform the way even modern Law is nowadays perceived and practiced in India[27]. In order to do so, we will especially build on Werner F. Menskis study Hindu Law : The search for appropriateness[28].

 

1) First of all it is important to note that if law is the central concept in Western societies around which social organization is structured, other cultures know different concepts which can be seen as homeomorphic equivalents[29] to law, meaning equivalents that assume a similar function in the different cultural context as law does in our cultural context[30]. The Indian homeomorphic equivalent to law is dharma[31]. It should be noted that starting from the Indian dharma, we may find religion as a European equivalent. There is thus no symmetric equivalence and the notion of dharma includes realities left aside by law and vice-versa. Dharma is a noun formed with the suffix ma from a root dhar or dhr. The root expresses actions such as to hold, bear, carry, maintain, preserve, keep. Hence dharma is the way in which, or the means by which, one holds, bears, carries, or maintains, and, in accordance with semantic development common in Sanskrit, it means not only the way of doing these things, but also the way of doing them. Dharma, then, is the way in which one ought to hold, bear, carry, or maintain. On a cosmic level, dharma is the way in which one maintains everything, the way in in which the cosmos or the balance in the cosmos, is maintained. At the micro level, dharma is the way in which every constituent element of the cosmos contributes its share to maintaining the overall balance. Each element has its own dharma, its svadharma. As long as each element of the cosmos performs its specific svadharma, the overall balance does not suffer. As soon as an element, however, deviates from its own dharma, that is, commits adharma, the balance is disturbed.[32] We can note that although dharma is a universal concept, it insists on diversity by recognizing that each element of the whole must follow its own dharma or svadharma in order to contribute to the overall dharma. 2) Thus it may appear as less surprising that the most striking element of Hindu law throughout has been its unlimited diversity and flexibility, which observers have far too often reduced to a few basic items, and have taken out of context. Hindu law strongly emphasizes the rhetoric and practice of plurality, diversity, and of relative justice, displaying tolerance almost to the point of selfless extinction () Legal diversity forms such an essential part of Hindu legal philosophy that uniformity of legal rules can be seen as a manifestation of injustice ()[33]. 3) Dharmas foundation and its sanction are religious, but it is essentially social in the sense that, in a social order visualized as one with the natural order, the individual who obeys its precepts performs a duty which is as much social as religious. () for authors committed to the religious significance of actions, societys essential end is the realization of dharma, when each individual can put his duties into effect. So their structure of law has dharma as its axis. But even in India religious aspirations do not monopolise all human activity. () Hindus contrast with dharma (which is the good) both artha (the useful) and kama (the pleasurable) which also motivate human behaviour[34]. 4) Besides a recognition of a pluralism and relativity in the notion of dharma which is linked to its situation-specific spirit, there thus appears another factor of pluralism. Human life is not only seen as the reflexion of a perfect dharmic order in the real world. Artha and kama also have their word to say. The view of a dharmic order cannot be equated to modern visions of order on which modern Western law is based. Indeed in the latter, order is equated to rational transparency and organization. The social ordering of society should reflect an abstract rational order and the legal system or universal law is thus seen before all as a means of uniformizing life according to the standards of Reason. It appears as a cruisade against chaos, which seems to be the modern perception of pluralism, and against ambiguity[35]. In the Indian perception we do not find the same idea of an abstract dharmic system which would have to impose itself on society as the very systemic and abstract nature of such a system is incompatible with the notion of dharma, although one can observe, since more or less a century tendencies towards an essentializing of these conceptions which do lead to very essentialized outlooks on Hinduism which come close Western systemic views[36]. Thus living laws have always been recognized and ways of articulating it with the general notion of dharma had to be found. While the classical period undoubtedly placed a duty on every individual to contribute to the maintenance of order at any one moment, the precise nature of that duty depends on social context. This is evident from the complex concept of varnashramadharma, the duty of an individual according to caste and stage of life () In seeking to circumscribe dharma for individual cases, important questions must have arisen about the relationship of the various local and family customs and the smriti rules, especially about the relationship between custom and dharma and, at a deeper levelbetween individual discretion and divine Order. () In Manusmriti  2.6 and 2.12 () we find reference to four sources, which tells us a lot about the living Hindu law : The whole Veda is the first source of dharma, next smriti and the virtuous conduct of those who know (the scriptures well), also the example of good people and finally the individual conscience. The Veda, the customs of good people, and ones own satisfaction they declare to be visibly the fourfold means of defining dharma.[37]. If the first two sources of law are not too problematic to grasp from a Western legal point of view, a few words should be said on the last two. Sadacara, the third source of dharma can be translated as model behaviour. I will follow here Menskis more anthropological than philosophical approach for whom () we should look upon sadacara as the major source of dharma, and thus of Hindu law () in the real life of almost all Hindus, recourse to scriptural was then (as it is now) a matter of secondary importance, a kind of last resort. There is no disagreement that sadacara can refer in various ways to custom, better perhaps good custom.[38] As for the source of dharma in individual conscience it should be clear that we are not in a modern individualistic context with a completely abstractly autonomous will. As Raimon Panikkar puts it, in the Indian Worldview the human being is a knot in the web of Reality[39], he is basically a being interlinked with the rest of reality towards which it rather has duties than rights. Reference to the individual consciousness must be understood in the sense that it is in the individual that cosmic dharma meets with a specific situation and has to be turned into svadharma, the appropriate action in a given space and time and constellation of facts[40]. Thus not anything goes. 5) Law in an Indian context thus seems to have a plural nature, and may be seen as resting on three main foundations instead of only one consisting in general and impersonal norms. The following insights of Menski constitue a perfect introduction to the plural approach to Law which we will develop in the next section and which also emphasizes the fact that legal pluralism is not just a situation or more or less conflictual coexistence of a plurality of same style law or legal systems, but that Law is a pluralistic phenomenon which is grounded in, at least, three different fundamental mechanisms. For Menski, since sadacara should be primarily based on social norms, the Hindu texts would have to remain a residual source for it if evidence of custom was available. This confirms that the idealized self-controlled order of Hindu law was primarily achieved by two types of internal self-regulation, either through an invisible mental process (asking ones conscience) or through consultation within the immediate social environment. Both might never strike us (and did not appear to H.L.A. Hart) as a legal process if we remain fixated on formal legal methods. If we phrase this discussion in terms of dispute resolution, we see again that the state, and any formal sources of law, play at best a peripheral role in classical Hindu law, which remains premised on the supremacy of self-controlled ordering processes and thus relies heavily on customary laws.[41]

 

Building on these insights, let us now move to the presentation of a pluralist approach to Law such as it has been developed at the Laboratoire dAnthropologie Juridique de Paris (LAJP)[42] which will be complemented by the opening up of a truly intercultural and pluralist horizon such as advocated by Raimon Panikkar and the Intercultural Institute of Montreal.

 

Towards a Pluralist Approach to Law

 

At the LAJP legal pluralism has never really constituted a specific research area, although it is obvious that the question of pluralism was always present in its research. Indeed from the moment where one leaves the legal systems point of view for the actors perspective, one cannot but be confronted to the inscription of the actor in multiple networks[43], legal fields[44], semi-autonomous social fields[45] or worlds[46]. As for the question of the definition of Law and the link between legal anthropology and theory of law it was very explicitely stated in a seminal article for our Laboratory written by Michel Alliot in 1983 and which deals with the prerequisites of a non-ethnocentric definition of Law. For Michel Alliot, Whoever wants to understand the form and the meaning of the legal institutions of a society has great interest not to relate them to the institutions of his own society - the connection would be superficial - but to the universe of the society in which he observes them.[47]. He thus proposes a definition of the legal phenomenon which is emancipated from the link with the state, a specific set of norms or a particular rationality and which, he argues, can be found in all societies: Its generality stems from the fact that it is in the nature of man and of society. Being, is struggling, individually or collectively. () And the struggles of its members are not without danger for the group. In the domains a society considers as vital - and thereupon every society has its own conception- its existence is only possible insofar as its members control, to the extent they can, these struggles or at least the practices that result from them. Living in society, is therefore not only struggling, it is also agreeing on the legitimacy or the illegitimacy of these practices and on the consequences that shall be given to them. Social life calls for consensus. The phenomenon is general because it is linked to the nature of the individual (struggle) and to the requirements of life in society (consensus) . (...) The law of a society is thus ordered around the limits of the spheres of action of all the domains it considers as vital : it is at the same time consensus on these limits and practices, aimed at, or succeeding in, confirming or displacing them. Thus defined, law is not linked by its nature to the existence of a state, nor to the formulation of rules, nor to the recognition of its rationality.[48] Although the article also tackles different issues we will focus on one of its proposals, namely the idea of legal archetypes. As we have already noted above when we talked of dharma as an Indian homeomorphic equivalent to Western law, Law is always linked to a certain worldview, a certain way to envisage the order of the universe and of society, a certain mythos[49]. Alliot illustrates this by presenting three different legal archetypes. The first one is the archetype of identification, exemplified by ancient China. It is complemented by a logic of self-improvement through the respect of rites and by a logic of complementarity of opposites (yin and yang, li and fa, rites and law). The second is the archetype of differentiation  exemplified by ancient Egypt and animist Africa. It is complemented by an autocentered logic which leads those societies to value internal regulation over regulation coming from outside, and it also share in a logic of complementarity of differences, although usually more than two. The third is the archetype of submission exemplified by Islamic and Western civilization. It is complemented by a logic of deresponsibilization of society itself in favour of an exterior entity and which thinks in terms of opposites excluding each other. These archetypes have bee complemented since, introducing for example what I have called in respect to the Indian experience an archetype of articulation which articulates the elements of these three archetypes. But we will focus on them as they have turned out to point to three main foundations of Law, which tienne Le Roy has taken as the basis for his theory of multijuridisme or multilegalism[50], and which we have already encountered at the end of our last section. Multilegalism is not so much about the plurality in a same space, or even person if we think of Jacques Vanderlindens new legal pluralism[51], of laws or legal systems. It is not so much about pluralism of legal contents. It rather points to the pluralism of the legal phenomenon itself which is made of different building blocks which interact but are valued differently in diverse cultures in a general way, but also in diverse concrete situations. The archetype of submission has pointed to an imposed patterning of society via especially general and impersonal norms. The archetype of identification rather pointed towards an accepted ordering of society, where Bourdieus habitus or systems of lasting dispositions for action are prevalent. The archetype of differentiation revealed a more negotiated patterning of social relationships, where what is privileged is negotiation in reference to shared models of conduct and behaviour. The channel for the first is rather norms linked to a specific power (e.g. the state), for the second it is education and for the last it is custom[52]. As we can see we find here the Indian sources of Dharma, the written authorities, the good custom, and the upproval of ones conscience. But these three feet of Law, should not be frozen they are walking in order to reproduce society or solve conflicts. As Sally Falk Moore noted process is not only change  Processes of regularization include all the ways in which conscious efforts are made to build and/or reproduce durable social and symbolic orders. () The continuous making and reiterating of social and symbolic order is seen as an active process, not as something which, once achieved, is fixed. The view is taken that existing orders are endlessly vulnerable to being unmade, remade, and transformed, and that even maintaining and reproducing themselves, staying as they are, should be seen as a process. [53] In that line the three feet of Law are just a photograph permitting to see the different mechanisms at play in their originality, but real life is the film, where we move from a recognition of alterity to its complex and dynamic interactions. That is why in order to understand the legal game in a given situation, tienne Le Roy advocates to play the game of laws which consists of ten squares, the last being the square of the rules of the legal game that the research has been able to identify in a given situation. As I have already presented this approach in a former publication in the Indian Socio-Legal Journal[54], let us just briefly remind its basic traits here :

 

The game of laws is a model of a processual approach to Law which has emerged through research of the Laboratoire danthropologie juridique de Paris in the domain of African land law and agricultural reforms and for research in the domain of the justice of minors before being presented as a more general theoretical framework.  It privileges two essential poles : the point of view of the observer and the individual and collective goals that are sought to be achieved. It focuses on the dynamic character of Law and thus takes further and complements Michel Alliots more structural model of the legal archetypes.

 

The model is presented in the form of a jeu de loie, a French game similar to the British Snakes and Ladders game, with ten squares leading to the rules of the social game, and on which players do not move by throwing dice but by moving according to the social and legal positions from which he/she can expect to win (or to lose) advantages in the social game[55]. 1. We enter the game with the identification of the statuses of the involved actors, as there are no abstract individuals but that human beings are always part of diverse networks, 2. We then move to the resources that they can mobilize in the game and which can be material, ideological, human 3. These resources will be used according to certain conducts which can be more long or short term oriented (strategies or tactics). 4. The actions will be lead according to certain logics, which can for instance be in the legal field of a more institutional or of a more functional nature 5. We then have to have a look at the geographical scale on which the game is taking place. And it is important that for the same case different scales may be relevant, according for example to the resources the diverse actors are able to mobilize. These scales can go from the most global (whole world), to the most local (individual) with in-between for example the regional, national, federal levels etc 6. But the game is not only played in space but also in time. It is thus important to look at the different time processes which can also overlap, from microprocesses of a few days up to megaprocesses of a few centuries or more. 7. The next question is the identification of the forums for interaction and of their nature (conflictual, cooperative for example), 8. This leads to the choice of the patterning of the relationships or the social orders or social orderings 9. Last but not least in every game there are stakes. They may not be the same for all participants and may be more or less explicit or implicit. There can also be more long term or more short term stakes  10. Going through all these cases, permits in the end to identify the rules of the game which can consist in diverse mixes of general and impersonal norms, models of conduct and behaviour and habitus and their imposition, negotiation or acceptation.

 

Obviously it appears that the observed reality cannot be made completely transparent and that changes in any of the squares will result in changes in the other squares. But this lack of transparency rather than a flaw rather appears as inevitable once one really allows oneself to leave the comfort of neat and clear systems in order to enter into the complexity of social life.

 

On a very general comparative level, tienne Le Roy[56] proposes the following table to indicate how different cultures may value differently the three feet of Law[57], in their over all organization :

 

Legal traditions

Privileged Foundation

Second Foundation

Third Foundation

Western / Christian

GIN[58]

MCB[59]

SLD[60]

African / Animist

MCB

SLD

GIN

Asian / Confucian

SLD

MCB

GIN

Arab / Muslim

GIN

SLD

MCB

 

 

Let me just note that we should keep in mind that the jeu des lois reflects an anthropocentric social sciences approach. It could be useful to introduce another first square before the one of the statuses of the actors : the one of our diverse worldviews in which the whole legal game is embedded. Indeed, there are worldvisions which are less anthropocentered than ours and more cosmocentered or theocentered[61]. This would change the whole perspective on our cosmic or divine game. But this is more of the realm of an intercultural approach to Law[62] that we will present as a horizon after our presentation of the game of laws. If we follow Menskis developments it would appear that the Indian view would be in line with what tienne Le Roy has described for the Asian / Confucian world. This remark immediately makes appear that although an underlying structure may be the same, different legal universes still behold their specific flavour. On a structural level we could note that the Confucian view of Law is dualistic, in the sense that it explicitely recognizes li (rites) and fa (law) as tools for upholding the social harmony. In contrast, the Indian view as we have shown above is pluralistic, recognizing explicitely three different foundations of law (if we do not take into consideration the difference between shruti and smriti). But the comparative challenge takes us further[63].

 

We must indeed recognize that in our presentation we have for the moment stayed in a Western perspective because we start out from what we consider as homeomorphic equivalents to our law but that homeomorphism is not symmetric. Thus for example, if in our culture the implicit presupposition is that Law is Man-centered its homeomorphic equivalents may be God or Cosmos-centered[64], which may change the whole picture in a genuine dialogue. It is useful here to keep in mind the horizon towards which Robert Vachon is pointing in his critical article on legal pluralism where he advocates the need for a diatopical and dialogical method : we must recognize that the question of homeomorphic equivalents to Law or to legal pluralism is already a situated question and is thus not a universal question, although it may appear to be so from our cultural window. Robert Vachon thus underlines the need to approach of Law and legal pluralism rather in terms of symbols than of concepts. For him the study of legal pluralism is () the study of this common horizon (myth) or reality which some call law and legal and others dharma etc. and that we have agreed to refer to as legal pluralism while we could also have called it dharmic pluralism.[65]

 

If it seems as important to try to understand the complex interminglings of diverse traditional and modern trends in the reflexions on the shaping of the contemporary states and their legal policies[66] as to work out the specificity of diverse worldviews and the conditions of a genuine dialogue[67], in the Indian context we could for the moment probably subscribe to Menskis agenda who notes that The vigorous debates in South Asia today on how to harmonize local legal norms and international legal expectations therefore point to the current reformulation of an ancient truth. It is now being realized in South Asia that the mechanics of legal positivism cannot provide meaningful justice to all people. () Justice remains a situation-sensitive, culture-specific matter. Safeguarding justice still requires searching for holistic solutions to problems in a particular context at a particular time, and this process cannot avoid recognizing what local people think is correct. What is right and what is wrong, in other words dharma, rests on many feet, as before. The modern state is ultimately unable to do anything but keep a watch over processes of negotiation. Thus, modern South Asia, stimulated as much by Hindu as by Muslim, Buddhist and Jaina ideas about justice and the good life, is now more openly than before rejecting legal messages from the West that emphasize state-focused approaches to law and legal regulation to the exclusion of the other spheres. Post-modern India has begun to rediscover and actively re-employ the ancient Indian model of Hindu self-controlled order and now tries to reformulate the old ideas in new ways. This does not necessarily lead to a hinduisation of India as many modernity-obsessed observers immediately fear. Recourse to Hindu concepts, wether explicit or implicit, has created a more justice-oriented understanding of modern law, which can hardly be treated as a negative development. ()While in economic and in other terms, globalization is a most powerful social force even in the Indian subcontinent, the legal field is one of the arenas in which tradition visibly asserts its modernity and where diversity demonstrates its continuing intrinsic link with unity. The universalistic foundations of Indian cultures generally, and particularly of Hindu culture, thus provide a culture-specific model for sustainable legal development of the future ()[68].

 

It seems that Menskis invitation invites us to reflect upon legal pluralism in India, by acknowledging Indias traditionally pluralist approach to Law. This move beyond legal pluralism, towards more pluralist theories of Law, in line with traditional Indian conceptions of Law meets with the preoccupations of some general approaches in the field of legal anthropology which try to move towards more plural legal theories. Despite the enrichment to the understanding of the Indian situation the shift of perspective from legal pluralism to a pluralist approach to Law thus seems to have more general stakes. These in turn may be tackled more easily if we accept to learn from the Indian experience.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 



[1] Panikkar Raimon, 1990,  The Myth of Pluralism , Harry James Carger (ed.), Invisible Harmony. Essays on Contemplation and Responsibility, USA, Fortress Press, 210 p (52-91), p 55 & 57.

[2] Whenever I will write  Law  with a capital  L  in this article, I am referring to Law as legal phenomena, which is not reduced to what is usually understood as law as general and impersonal rules more or less directly linked to the State. By using Law, I refer to that which puts forms and puts into forms the reproduction of societies and their solving of conflicts Western type law is just one aspect of Law, which may be very dominating in some contexts, but may only represent the tip of the iceberg of legal phenomena in other contexts. This view of Law will be further developed in this article in the third section.

[3] This is a research center on legal anthropology of the University Paris 1 Panthon Sorbonne. A lot of research carried out at the LAJP is available on http://www.dhdi.org.

[4] The IIM also has an internet site : http://www.iim.qc.ca.

[5] See already for this endeavor Christoph Eberhard,  Towards an Intercultural Legal Theory - The Dialogical Challenge , Social & Legal Studies. An International Journal, volume 10, number 2, june 2001, p 171-201 ; Challenges and Prospects for the Anthropology of Law. A Francophone Perspective , Newsletter of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, nXXXV, 2002, p 47-68 ;  Dialogue with Jacques Vanderlinden. Part 1 , Newsletter of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, nXXXVII, 2003, p 72-79. This texts can also be consulted at http://www.dhdi.org.

[6] Franz von Benda-Beckmann,  Whos Afraid of Legal Pluralism ? , in Pradhan Rajendra (ed.), Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political Development. Papers of  the XIIIth International Congress of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, Vol. III, Kathmandu, ICNEC,  2003,  417 p (275-298). All the upcoming page references refer to this article.

[7] In our terminology, we would rather speak of his definition of Law.

[8] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 276

[9] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 277

[10] I am following here Claude Lvi-Strauss definition which sees ethnography, ethnology and anthropology as three moments of a same endeavor. Ethnography is concerned with description of different societies. Ethnology with the working out of fundamental models of these societies and anthropology is concerned with elaborating general theories on the life of human beings in society via a comparison of the data which has been produced through ethnography and ethnology.

[11] See also Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 277. We do very much agree with Franz von Benda Beckmann when he writes p 278 : So before one enters into conceptual debates, one should be clear in ones appreciation of the different academic and professional enterprises, their limitations and implications, and take them into account when promoting ones own understanding or criticizing that of others. In my view, many of the discussions about law or legal pluralism suffer from the tendency to bring these different objectives and resultant concepts down onto a one-dimensional level of discussion, at which authors look for the one correct or useful concept for both lawyers and social scientists. It is particularly under the name of theory that many scholars claim universal value for their concept in an absolutist manner. In our view this remark underlines the importance of what we call diatopical and dialogical in the line of the writings of Raimon Panikkar and Robert Vachon (see for example Christoph Eberhard,  Towards an Intercultural Legal Theory - The Dialogical Challenge , Social & Legal Studies. An International Journal, volume 10, number 2, june 2001, p 171-201 & Christoph Eberhard, Challenges and Prospects for the Anthropology of Law. A Francophone Perspective, Newsletter of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, 2002, nXXXV, p 47-68).

[12] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 276

[13] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 276

[14] See for example Bell John,  Comparative Law and Legal Theory , Krawietz Werner, MacCormick Neil, von Wright George Henrik (ds.), Prescriptive Formality and Normative Rationality in Modern Legal Systems. Festschrift for Robert S. Summers, Berlin, Duncker & Humbolt, 1994, p 19-31 ; Legrand Pierre,  How to compare now ? , Legal Studies, n 16, 1996, p 232-242

[15] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 281-282.

[16] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 282-284

[17] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 285-286.

[18] Von Benda-Beckman op. cit. p 286.

[19] See in this context the very interesting paper of Keebet von Benda-Beckmann,  The Contexts of Law, in Pradhan Rajendra (ed.), Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political Development. Papers of the XIIIth International Congress of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, Vol. III, Kathmandu, ICNEC,  2003,  417 p (299-315). She writes : As a sensitizing concept, legal pluralism is generally taken to refer to a component system of norms, or constellation of various legal systems, though it is usually emphasized that the term system should not be taken too literally. () Law is not an amorphous set of norms and principles but neither is it a tightly structured system. () Law typically consists of clustered sets of norms, principles, concepts and procedures. And such clusters provide cognitive and normative and institutional contexts for interaction. (p 299).

[20] Keebet von Benda-Beckmann, op. cit. p 299.

[21] Monique Nuitjen,  Land and the Law in Mexico : Towards a Force Fields Approach in Legal Anthropolgy , in Pradhan Rajendra (ed.), Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political Development. Papers of  the XIIIth International Congress of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, Vol. III, Kathmandu, ICNEC,  2003,  417 p (353-368) : p 364-365.

[22] He writes :  There is no reason to suppose that, in systems of customary law or in western state laws, the general population which observes a law has any great difficulty in accepting mutually incompatible norms. Thus, the notion that legal norms are organized into systems is unsustainable. , Gordon Woodman,  Why There Can be no Map of Law , in Pradhan Rajendra (ed.), Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law in Social, Economic and Political Development. Papers of  the XIIIth International Congress of the Commission on Folk Law and Legal Pluralism, Vol. III, Kathmandu, ICNEC,  2003,  417 p (383-392).

[23] Vanderlinden Jacques,  Return to Legal Pluralism : Twenty Years Later , Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, n 28, 1989, pp. 149-157 & Vanderlinden Jacques,  Vers une nouvelle conception du pluralisme juridique , Revue de la Recherche Juridique - Droit prospectif, XVIII, 2, 1993, p. 573-583

[24] See Franz von Benda-Beckmann op. cit. p 292-294. For a good illustration more specifically in the field of the choice between rather law centered or order and dispute centered research see also Roberts S., Order and Dispute. An Introduction to Legal Anthropology, Middlesex, Penguin, 1979, p 185-373

[25]  See in that sense already Christoph Eberhard,  Penser le pluralisme juridique de manire pluraliste. Dfi pour une thorie interculturelle du Droit , Cahiers dAnthropologie du Droit, n2, Paris, Karthala, 2003, p 51-63

[26] If what is called today  Hinduism  can be seen as standing for pluralism, as we will develop it here, the roots of this term should not be forgotten. It is all the more important to underline them because of the more or less conscious relationships between  Hinduism  and  Hindutva . First, from a purely linguistic point of view, I am quite cautious about any isms which seem to denote a thrust towards unification and theory, or even ideology, e.g. socialism, liberalism, Marxism, structuralism, etc. and I would even add such isms as pluralism, multiculturalism, interculturalism. One should be aware of what isms imply. Second, I would like to quote five insights by Ashis Nandy, Shikha Trivedy, Shail Mayaram, Achyut Yagnik in Creating a Nationality. The Ramjanmabhumi Movement and Fear of the Self, India, Oxford India Paperbacks, 212 p (56-63) : As repeated ad nauseum these days, the word Hindu is of Arabic/Persian origin and has exactly the same meaning etymologically as the word India which is of Graeco-Roman origin. None of the Hindu sacred texts even once mentions the word Hindu. Both of these words have served for outsiders unacquainted with the complexities of the country, as a generic name for the different, mainly non-Islamic, but also non-Christian, communities living in the subcontinent. After this introductory statement and after mentioning the processes of Hindu responses to the colonial state in the 19th century, the authors note concerning the new Hinduism : First, it defensively rejected or devalued the little cultures of India as so many indices of the countrys backwardness and as prime candidates for integration within the Hindu/national mainstream. Instead the new Hindus sought to chalk out a new pan-Indian religion called Hinduism that would be primarily classical, Brahmanic, Vedantic and, therefore, not an embarrassment to the modern or semi-modern Indians in touch with the more civilized parts of the world. () Second, the redefined version of Hinduism allowed those who saw the new religion more as an ideology than as a faith, to use Hinduism as an instrument of political mobilization, la European-style national ideology. () Third, this Hinduism sought to masculinize the self-definition of the Hindus and, thus, martialize the community. () Fourth, Hindu nationalism not only accepted modern science and technology and their Baconian social philosophy, it also developed a totally uncritical attitude towards any Western knowledge system that seemed to contribute to the development and sustenance of state power and which promised to homogenize the Indian population. () In other words, even the Hindus who would constitue the Hindu rashtra are not expected to be Hindus in the traditional sense. The traditional Hindus are seen as too diverse, feminized, irrational, unversed in the inticacies of the modern world, and too pantheistic, pagan, gullible and anarchic to run a proper state. So, the emphasis is on the new version of Hindus emerging in metropolitan India, with one foot in western education and values, the other in simplified versions of classical thought now available in commoditifiable form in the urban centres of India.

[27] R.S. Khare writes in that context :  Though exasperating to a modern social reformer and a human rights advocate, this deeply-ingrained cultural lexicon of karma-dharma and divine justice complex is shared widely by ordinary Hindus, Buddhists, Jains, and Sikhs in India. It is the peoples jurisprudence, shaping the prevalent notions of social fairness and justice. It goes through periodic cycles of rigidity, reform, flexibility, as various saints, reformers, and leaders try to explicate it from time to time. It encounters petitions, protests, and upheavals, as well as a rising devotional faith in the intervening power of the divine will.  in  Elusive Social Justice, Distant Human Rights : Untouchable Womens Struggles and Dilemmas in Changing India , Cultural Diversity and Social Discontent. Anthropological Studies on Contemporary India, New Delhi, Sage Publications, 1998, 282 p

[28] Werner F. Menski,  Hindu law : the search for appropriateness , in Comparative Law in Global Context : the Legal Systems of Asia and Africa, London, Platinium, 2000, 590 p (138-208). For a good introduction to the principles of Hindu Law also see Sunderlal T. Desai, Introduction, Principles of Hindu Law, Bombay, N. M. Tripathi Private Limited, 1990, p 1-65.

[29] For an explanation of the notion of  homeomorphic equivalent  and the  diatopical hermeneutics  which is linked to it see Panikkar Raimon,  Is the notion of Human Rights a Western Concept ? , Interculture, Vol. XVII, n 1, Cahier 82, 1984, p 28-47 and also Christoph Eberhard,  Towards an Intercultural Legal Theory - The Dialogical Challenge , Social & Legal Studies. An International Journal, volume 10, number 2, june 2001, p 171-201 

[30] See Sinha Surya Prakash, 1995a,  Legal Polycentricity , Petersen H., Zahle H. (eds.), Legal Polycentricity : Consequences of Pluralism in Law, UK, Dartmouth, 1995, 245 p (31-69)

[31] See for example Sinha Surya Prakash, 1995,  Non-Universality of Law - The Indian way of life , Nanda Ved P., Sinha Surya Prakash (eds.), Hindu Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 357 p (73-77)

[32] Rocher Ludo, 1978,  Hindu Conceptions of Law , Nanda Ved P., Sinha Surya Prakash (ds.), Hindu Law and Legal Theory, Great Britain, Dartmouth, The International Library of Essays in Law and Legal Theory Series, 1996, 357 p (3-25)

[33] Menski, op. cit. p 143.

[34] Lingat Robert, The Classical Law of India, New Delhi, Oxford University Press, 1998 (1973), 305 p (4-5).

[35] See for example on these questions Bauman Zygmunt, Legislators and Interpreters - On Modernity, Post-modernity and Intellectuals, Great Britain, Polity Press, 1987, 209 p and Bauman Zygmunt, Modernity and Ambivalence, Great Britain, Polity Press, 1993 (1991), 285 p

[36] See for example Javeed Alam,  Hindus and Others in the Making of the Nation , in Javeed Alam, India. Living with modernity, India, Oxford University Press, 1999, 241 p (103-127) and the chapter  Creating a Nationality  in Nandy Ashis, Trivedy Shikha, Mayaram Shail, Yagnik Achyut, 1997, Creating a Nationality. The Ramjanmabhumi Movement and Fear of the Self, India, Oxford India Paperbacks, 212 p (56-80).

[37] Menski, op. cit. p 153-154

[38] Menski, op. cit. p 156

[39] Panikkar R.,  Is the notion of Human Rights a Western Concept ? , Interculture, Vol. XVII, n 1, Cahier 82, 1984, p 28-47, p 42.

[40] It can be interesting to compare this with the description Rebecca Redwood French gives of the kaleidoscopic traditional legal system of Buddhist Tibet, which is also centered on the  individuals  enlightened mind and takes the shape of a mandala :  () the mandala represented all the basic ideas of Buddhism : karma, the everpresentness of realms, radical particularity, the cyclical nature of existence, the Buddha core. The government of Tibet itself was understood as a multilayered mandala with successive levels of periphery leading to a core in Lhasa, the home of the Buddha. Hierarchy, social categories, power relations, legal levels from the households to the Hight Court, all accorded with this representation. The individual mind at the center of the personal mandala was also understood as the center of the legal universe, and the mandala reiterated in symbolic form the movement of the legal system. Just as Buddhas emanated from the core and aspirants in meditation, moved from the outer to the inner doors of the mandala, so the legal system was understood as flexible, allowing movement up and down and between different procedures, forums and levels. in Rebecca Redwood French, The Golden Yoke. The Legal Cosmology of Buddhist Tibet, United States of America, Cornell University Press, 1995, 404 p. It can also be interesting to consult Christoph Eberhard,  Opening Up Spaces for Peace. A Dialogical and Transmodern Challenge , Indian Socio-Legal Journal, Vol. XXIX, n 1 & 2, p 1-14 which deals with the question of an anthropological approach to Law via a Buddhist perspective.

[41] Menski, op. cit. p 156. And

[42] Laboratory of Legal Anthropology of Paris of the University Paris 1 Panthon Sorbonne.

[43] See for example Eberhard Christoph (ed.), Le Droit en perspective interculturelle. Images rflchies de la pyramide et du rseau, numro thmatique de la Revue Interdisciplinaire dՃtudes Juridiques n49, 2002, 346 p.

[44] see for example Nuitjen op. cit.

[45] See Sally Falk Moore,  Law and Social Change : The Semi-Autonomous Social Field as an Appropriate Subject of Study , Law and Society Review, Summer, 1973, p 719-746

[46] Boltanski Luc, Thvenot Laurent, De la justification - Les conomies de la grandeur, Mesnil-sur-lEstre, Gallimard, Col. nrf essais, 1991, 483 p

[47] Alliot Michel,  Anthropologie et juristique. Sur les conditions de lՎlaboration dune science du droit , Bulletin de Liaison du Laboratoire dAnthropologie Juridique de Paris, n 6, 1983, p 83-117, p 91. This article has been republished in Michel Alliot, Le droit et le service public au miroir de l'anthropologie, (dit par Camille Kuyu), Paris, Karthala, 2003, 400 p (283-305). All non-English quotations have bee translated into English from the original by me.

[48] Alliot op. cit., p 85-86.

[49]  Myth represents the invisible horizon on which we project our notions of the real. Panikkar Raimon, 1979, Myth, Faith and Hermeneutics - Cross-cultural studies, USA, Paulist Press, 500 p (30). It is  that in which we believe so much that we do not believe that we believe it Vachon Robert, 1995, Guswenta ou limpratif interculturel - Premire partie : Les fondements interculturels de la paix, Interculture, Vol. XXVIII, n 2, cahier n 127, 80 p (38) this issue of Interculture is also available in English.

[50] Le Roy tienne, 1998a,  Lhypothse du multijuridisme dans un contexte de sortie de modernit , Lajoie Andr, MacDonald Roderick A., Janda Richard, Rocher Guy (ds.), Thories et mergence du droit : pluralisme, surdtermination et effectivit, Bruxelles, Bruylant/Thmis , 266 p (29-43)

[51] see Vanderlinden op. cit.

[52] At the Laboratoire custom is seen as a specific procedure rather than a specific content, which is more based on the negotiation of accepted solutions in reference to shared models of conduct and behaviour, rather than the imposition of a general, impersonal and preexisting rule in order to solve a conflict. See Le Roy tienne,  Lesprit de la coutume et lidologie de la loi , colloque de lARSOM, Bruxelles, La Connaissance du Droit en Afrique, Bruxelles, ARSOM, 1984, p 210-240

[53]Sally Falk Moore, Law as Process - An Anthropological Approach, Great Britain, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983, 263 p (6).

[54] See  Human Rights and Intercultural Dialogue. An Anthropological Perspective , Indian Socio-Legal Journal, Vol. XXVII, p 99-120, especially the section  The Game of Laws (Le jeu des lois) A Dynamic Approach to Law , p 114-118. The approach is the backbone of tienne Le Roys book, Le jeu des lois. Une anthropologie  dynamique  du Droit, France, LGDJ, Col. Droit et Socit, Srie anthropologique,1999, 415 p

[55] Le Roy op. cit. p. 35 ff

[56] tienne Le Roy, op. cit. p 202

[57] GIN : general and impersonal norms ; MCB : models of conduct and behaviour ; SLD : systems of lasting dispositions.

[58] GIN : general and impersonal norms.

[59] MCB : models of conduct and behaviour.

[60] SLD : systems of lasting dispositions.

[61] See for example Panikkar Raimon, The Cosmotheandric Experience - Emerging Religious Consciousness, New York, Orbis Books, 1993, 160 p

[62] For the distinction beween an intercultural approach to Law which takes predominantly place on the level of myhtos and an intercultural legal theory which is rather located in the domain of logos see Eberhard Christoph,  Towards an Intercultural Legal Theory - The Dialogical Challenge , Social & Legal Studies. An International Journal, volume 10, number 2, june 2001, p 171-201

[63] For a presentation of Alliots archetypes complemented by the Indian archetype of artculation and the archetype of rationlization see Eberhard Christoph, Droits de lhomme et dialogue interculturel, Paris, ditions des crivains, 2002, 398 p (129-171).

[64] Panikkar,  Raimon,  Is the notion of Human Rights a Western Concept ? , Interculture 82, 1984, p. 28-47 (42)

[65] Vachon Robert, 1990,  LՎtude du pluralisme juridique - une approche diatopique et dialogale , Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, n 29, p 163-173

[66] tienne Le Roys anthropology of Law is explicitely centered on these questions. See for example Le Roy tienne, Les Africains et l'Institution de la Justice, Paris, Dalloz, 2004, 283 p

[67] This has been Robert Vachons main field of reflexion. For a synthetic overview see  IIM and its journal : an intercultural alternative and an alternative interculturalism , Interculture, p 4-74.

[68] Menski op. cit. p 186-187.